Some relationships between evolutionary stability criteria in games

Similar documents
CS 486/686 Lecture 17 2-Player Normal-Form Games 1. Determine dominant-strategy equilibria of a 2-player normal form game.

Static (or Simultaneous- Move) Games of Complete Information

Analyze different types of non zero sum games. Hawk vs. Dove game. Advertising problem. Problem of companies polluting the environment.

Table A1.1: The Iteration Path Game

Chapter 9: Static Games and Cournot Competition

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory Analyzing Normal-Form Games

Identification of the oligopoly solution concept in a differentiated-products industry

Analysis on the Impact of Government Policies towards Technological Innovation Using Evolutionary Game Theory

SEQUENTIAL DECISIONS IN THE COLLEGE ADMISSIONS PROBLEM. Jose Alcalde and Antonio Romero-Medina *

Equilibrium Selection and the Role of Information in Repeated. Matching Markets

Adaptive Properties and Memory of a System of Interactive Agents: A Game Theoretic Approach

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS AND STATISTICS Attempt all the questions. The allocation of marks is shown in brackets.

SI Game Theory, Fall 2008

Existence of a Pareto optimal social interaction outcome with non-binary preferences

Multilateral negotiations with private side deals: a multiplicity example. Abstract

Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with Contracts

Equilibria in an infinite horizon game with an incumbent, entry and switching costs

Analysis of Corporate Social Responsibility Based on Evolutionary Game Theory

WEAK AND STRICT DOMINANCE: A UNIFIED APPROACH

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 2. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Models of Language Evolution

Agility in Repeated Games: An Example

Mixed strategies and iterative elimination of strongly dominated strategies: an experimental investigation of states of knowledge

LECTURE 6: MULTIAGENT INTERACTIONS

This paper is not to be removed from the Examination Halls

Incentives for Market Research: Preemption and Learning Effects

Understanding UPP. Alternative to Market Definition, B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, forthcoming.

Graham Romp Dynamic Game Theory.

Economics Letters 88 (2005) Efficient entry. Daniel Quint, Liran EinavT

Game Theory DR. ÖZGÜR GÜRERK UNIVERSITY OF ERFURT WINTER TERM 2012/13. What can we model as a game?

Matching: The Theory. Muriel Niederle Stanford and NBER. October 5, 2011

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Chapter 12. A Game Theoretic Approach to Strategic Behavior

Welfare properties of argumentation-based semantics 1

Modeling of competition in revenue management Petr Fiala 1

ECO 610: Lecture 9. Oligopoly, Rivalry, and Strategic Behavior

Anti-Sharing as a Theory of Partnerships and Firms

Sales Restriction, Quality Selection and the Mode of Competition

HIERARCHICAL decision making problems arise naturally

arxiv: v1 [econ.em] 12 Jul 2018

Process of sustainable project development with Rubik s Cube using Game Theory interpretations

Modelling Beliefs in Games with Generalized. Preferences and Other Essays

AN ASCENDING AUCTION FOR INTERDEPENDENT VALUES: UNIQUENESS AND ROBUSTNESS TO STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

EXAMINATION #4 VERSION C General Equilibrium and Market Power November 24, 2015

UNIVERSITY OF CAPE COAST CAPE COAST - GHANA BASIC OLIGOPOLY MODELS

Refinements of Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Co-evolution of strategies and update rules in the prisoner s dilemma game on complex networks

"Solutions" to Non-constant Sum Games

Strategic Alliances, Joint Investments, and Market Structure

INDUSTRIAL ECONOMICS, WITH APPLICATIONS TO E-COMMERCE An Option for MSc Economics and MSc E-Commerce Autumn Term 2003

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

LECTURE 7: Reaching Agreements

Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries

A Walrasian Theory of Commodity Money: Paradoxical Results *

ECN 3103 INDUSTRIAL ORGANISATION

ECON 2100 (Fall 2018 Section 11) Exam #3B

ECON 2100 (Fall 2018 Section 11) Exam #3A

Entry decisions and bidding behavior in sequential first-price procurement auctions: An experimental study

Renting or Selling A Strategic Choice in a Durable Good Market

Analytic Preliminaries for Social Acceptability of Legal Norms &

Learning by Observing

On cleaner technologies in a transboundary pollution game

Simple Market Equilibria with Rationally Inattentive Consumers

Managerial Economics. Game Theory

Università degli Studi di Siena DIPARTIMENTO DI ECONOMIA POLITICA NICOLA DIMITRI. Cooperation with Strategy-Dependent Uncertainty Attitude

Durable goods with quality differentiation

Algorithmic Collusion For IO Reading Group

Advertising and Competition for Market Share between a New Good Producer and a Remanufacturer

Game Theory Exam, June 2015

Lecture 1 : The Diamond- Mortensen- Pissarides framework

Citation Journal of Integrated Creative Stud

Overcoming the Limitations of Utility Design for Multiagent Systems

UNIK Multiagent systems Lecture 5. Non-cooperative game theory. Jonas Moen

Markets and Strategy. Topics. Strategic Behavior. Intermediate Microeconomics

Price of anarchy in auctions & the smoothness framework. Faidra Monachou Algorithmic Game Theory 2016 CoReLab, NTUA

When the M-optimal match is being chosen, it s a dominant strategy for the men to report their true preferences

This paper is not to be removed from the Examination Halls

This paper is not to be removed from the Examination Halls

On the mode of Competition as a Collusive Perspective in Unionized Oligopoly

Citation for published version (APA): Kopányi, D. (2015). Bounded rationality and learning in market competition Amsterdam: Tinbergen Institute

Networks, Telecommunications Economics and Strategic Issues in Digital Convergence. Prof. Nicholas Economides. Spring 2006

Collusion. Sotiris Georganas. February Sotiris Georganas () Collusion February / 31

CARTEL STABILITY AND THE CURVATURE OF MARKET DEMAND. Luca Lambertini *

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

CS364B: Frontiers in Mechanism Design Lecture #1: Ascending and Ex Post Incentive Compatible Mechanisms

Oligopoly limit-pricing in the lab

Rent-setting in multiple winner rent-seeking contests

Activity Rules and Equilibria in the Combinatorial Clock Auction

The Robust Price of Anarchy of Altruistic Games

No THE MUSEUM PASS GAME AND ITS VALUE REVISITED. By Arantza Estévez-Fernández, Peter Borm, Herbert Hamers. January 2004 ISSN

Volume 29, Issue 4. Customization: Ideal Varieties, Product Uniqueness and Price Competition

Finance 510 Midterm #2 Practice Questions

Oligopoly Theory (11) Collusion

The 2x2 Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/2 (Lecture 8, Micro Theory I)

Sponsored Search Markets

Advanced Microeconomics Theory. Chapter 8: Game Theory and Imperfect Competition

Lecture 4: Will profits in reality be higher or lower than under Cournot? Tom Holden

14.01 Principles of Microeconomics, Fall 2007 Chia-Hui Chen November 7, Lecture 22

Who Thinks About the Competition? Managerial ability and strategic entry in US local telephone markets by Avi Goldfarb and Mo Xiao (2010)

Transcription:

Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 Some relationships between evolutionary stability criteria in games Martin Dufwenberg a,b, * a Center for Economic Research, Tilburg University, Tilburg, Netherlands b Department of Economics, Uppsala University, Sweden Received 7 January 1997; received in revised form 13 May 1997; accepted 2 June 1997 Abstract The relations between several evolutionary stability criteria are studied. 1997 Elsevier Science S.A. Keywords: Evolutionary stability JEL classification: C72 1. Introduction I study the relations between three old and two new criteria of evolutionary stability in games: evolutionary stability (Maynard-Smith and Price, 1973), neutral stability (Maynard-Smith, 1982), robustness against equilibrium entrants (Swinkels, 1992), robustness against admissible entrants, and robustness against iteratively admissible entrants. Combining new and old findings, the following picture emerges: Neutral stability is neither weaker nor stronger than robustness against equilibrium entrants. Each of these two criteria is neither weaker nor stronger than any of the two new criteria. Evolutionary stability is stronger than the other four criteria taken together. In some games no strategy satisfies any of the criteria. Section 2 contains results on the old criteria. Section 3 introduces, motivates, and states results involving the two new criteria. Section 4 summarizes most results in a table. Throughout, the analysis deals with mixed extension of finite symmetric 2-player normal form games (see Weibull, 1995 for a detailed presentation of such structures). The following notation is used: In any given game, A ± [ denotes either of the players set of (mixed) strategies (infinite-action unless singleton), and u:a 3 A R denotes the associated payoff function. With x, y [ A, u(x,y) is the payoff to strategy x when paired against strategy y. The notation? y 1 (1 2 )? x is used to denote the strategy which puts probability weight on y, etc. *Tel.: 146 18 182309; fax: 146 18 181478; e-mail: martin.dufwenberg@nek.uu.se 0165-1765/ 97/ $17.00 1997 Elsevier Science S.A. All rights reserved. PII S0165-1765(97)00195-X

46 M. Dufwenberg / Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 2. Results on established criteria The following well-known definitions specify conditions under which a strategy may be deemed more or less impregnable to evolutionary force: Definition 1. (Maynard-Smith and Price, 1973): x [ A is an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS) if ;y [ A, y ± x it holds that (i) u(x,x) $ u( y,x) and (ii) u(x,x) 5 u( y,x) u(x,y). u( y,y). Definition 2. (Maynard-Smith, 1982): x [ A is a neutrally stable strategy (NSS) if ;y [ A, y ± xit holds that (i) u(x,x) $ u( y,x) and (ii) u(x,x) 5 u( y,x) u(x,y) $ u( y,y). Definition 3. (Swinkels, 1992): x [ A is robust against equilibrium entrants (REE) if ' * [ (0,1) such that ;y [ A, y ± x and ; [ (0, *) it holds that y [ argmax u(z,? y 1 (1 2 )? x). It is immediate from the definitions that if x [ A is ESS then x is NSS. Swinkels (1992) shows that if x [ A is ESS then x is REE. Weibull (1995), Section 2.3.2, points out that in a game such that u(a,b) 5 u(c,d) ;a,b,c,d [ A (with A not singleton) any strategy is NSS but no strategy is REE, so neutral stability does not imply robustness against equilibrium entrants. The game G1 shows that no implication runs the other way: a 1,1 0,1 1,1 b 1,0 1,1 0,2 c 1,1 2,0 0,0 G 1 In G 1, the strategy a is not NSS (b can invade in the sense that condition (ii) of Definition 2 is violated). However, a is REE since ;y[a, y±a and ;.0 it holds that y[ argmaxz[a u(z,? y1 (12 )?a), as is easily verified. A strategy may be both NSS and REE without being ESS. This is an immediate consequence of the last result of the next section (base on G 6). z[a 3. Results involving two new criteria In order to motivate the two new stability criteria that will be introduced in this section, it is convenient to first consider a reformulation of the REE concept: Definition 39: x[ A is robust against equilibrium entrants (REE) if ' *[(0,1) such that ;y[ A, y±x it holds that (i) u(x,x)$u( y,x), and (ii) u(x,x)5u( y,x) [u(x,y).u( y,y) or ; [(0, *) it holds that y[ argmaxz[a u(z,? y1(12 )?x)]. Definition 39 is equivalent to Definition 3. To see this, suppose first that strategy x[a is REE according to Definition 3. Swinkels (1992) shows that (x,x) then must be a (proper) Nash equilibrium, so u(x,x)$u( y,x) ;y[a, implying that x meets condition (i) of Definition 39. That x also meets condition (ii) of Definition 39 is immediate. Conversely, suppose x[ A is REE according to Definition

M. Dufwenberg / Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 47 39. Given Swinkels (1992) finding that an ESS must be REE, it is easy to see that x then must be REE according to Definition 3. Definition 39 makes clear how the REE and ESS criteria are related. Both criteria imply that for x[a to pass the respective tests, it must be a best response against itself. The ESS criterion moreover requires that any alternative best reply y[a to x must do strictly worse than x against y. This is sufficient for x to be REE, but x passes the test also if y is not an equilibrium entrant in Swinkels (1992) sense. Condition (ii) of Definition 39 effectively excludes as potential invaders all those alternative best responses to x that lack a quality of post-entry optimality. In Swinkels (1992), p. 307, words, the REE criterion strikes a middle ground between the total absence of rationality assumed by evolutionary game theory and the strenuous rationality requirements of traditional game theory. However, it is not obvious that the only natural quality to impose on potential invaders is to assume they have the foresight to choose post-entry optimal strategies. A reasonable alternative might be to require entrants that are alternative best responses to x to choose strategies with some kind of decision-theoretic appeal. More generally, I suggest replacing conditions (ii) of Definition 1 to read u(x,x)5u( y,x) [u(x,y).u( y,y) ory[ R], where R# A contains the set of strategies that are rational according to some criterion. Gans (1995) studies evolutionary selection of beliefs and performs an exercise which can be interpreted within this framework. Translated to the present setting, he considers the cases where R is equal to respectively the set of strategies that are not strictly dominated and the set of rationalizable strategies (5those that survive iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies). However, in these particular cases no leeway is offered in addition to Definition 1, so Gans (1995) concepts are 1 equivalent to the ESS concept. Now two new criteria will be considered. These relate to the following defnition: 0 t t t21 t21 Definition 4. Let A 5A. For t51,2,..., define A recursively by A 5hx[A u there exists no y[a t 2 1 t 2 1 1 such that u( y,z)$u(x,z) ;z[a and u( y,z).u(x,z) for some z[a j. A is the set of admissible ` t strategies. > A is the set of iteratively admissible strategies. t50 According to Definition 4, a strategy is admissible iff 1 is weakly undominated. A strategy is iteratively admissible iff it survives iterated elimination of dominated strategies where at each round every dominated strategy is eliminated. It is well-known that (for the class of games under T 1 k ` t consideration) there exists T $0 such that ;k$0 it holds that [±A 5> A. Definition 5. x[ A is robust against admissible entrants (RAE) if ;y[ A, y±x it holds that (i) u(x,x)$u( y,x), and (ii) u(x,x)5u( y,x) [u(x,y).u( y,y) or x is not admissible]. Definition 6. x[ A is robust against iteratively admissible entrants (RIE) if ;y±x it holds that (i) u(x,x)$u( y,x), and (ii) u(x,x)5u( y,x) [u(x,y).u( y,y) or x is not iteratively admissible]. In promoting his REE criterion, Swinkels (1992), Fig. 2, provides an example of a game in which no ESS exist and nevertheless a strategy (which is REE) seems stable. The reader may verify that t50 1 To see why this happens, suppose x[a satisfies either of Gans criteria but yet is not ESS. Then there must exist a non-rationalizable strategy y[ A such that u( y,x)5u(x,x). However, since (x,x) must be a Nash equilibrium and any best reply to x then must be rationalizable it must hold that u( y,x),u(x,x). This is a contradiction.

48 M. Dufwenberg / Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 strategy is also RAE and RIE. However, these two criteria are in general neither weaker nor stronger than the REE criterion. The game G2 shows that neither of the two new criteria implies robustness against equilibrium entrants: a 1,1 0,1 2,1 b 1,0 1,1 0,1 c 1,2 1,0 1,1 G 2 In G, the strategy a is RAE and RIE but not REE (the dominated strategy b can invade). 2 On the other hand, robustness against equilibrium entrants does not imply any of the new criteria. This can be illustrated using the game G : 3 r s p r 1,1 2,0 0,2 s 0,2 1,1 2,0 p 2,0 0,2 1,1 G 3 In G, the strategy (r/31s/31p/3) is REE (cf. the discussion of Example 2.8 in Weibull (1995)), but 3 this strategy is neither RAE nor RIE. Neither of the two new criteria imply neutral stability. This can be shown using G, in which game 1 the strategy a is RAE and RIE but not NSS. Conversely, neutral stability does not imply any of the new criteria. This can be shown using a game such that u(a,b)5u(c,d) ;a,b,c,d[a (with A not singleton), in which any strategy is NSS but no strategy is RAE or RIE. In the games considered so far the sets of strategies which are RAE and RIE have coincided. It is obvious from the Definitions 5 and 6 that if x[a is RAE it must be RIE. The game G illustrates that 4 the converse is not true: d a 1,1 0,1 0,1 2,1 b 1,0 1,1 0,1 0,0 c 1,0 1,0 1,1 0,1 d 1,2 0,0 1,0 1,1 G 4 In G 4, a (which is the unique iteratively admissible strategy) is RIE. However, a is not RAE (the admissible strategy c can invade). It is well-known that strategies which are ES, NSS, or REE fail to exist in some games. The same goes for the RAE and RIE criteria. The game G 5 (from Ex. 2.7 in Weibull (1995)) even illustrates that the seemingly weak requirement that a strategy should meet any of the hitherto discussed criteria is incompatible with existence: a 1,1 0,1 0,1 b 0,1 1,1 1,0 c 1,0 0,1 1,1 G 5

M. Dufwenberg / Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 49 In G 5, no strategy satisfies any of the criteria discussed so far (the successful invaders under the NSS criterion discussed in Ex. 2.7 in Weibull (1995) work for the other criteria too). Finally, the game G6 shows that a strategy may simultaneously satisfy all the criteria of NSS, REE, RIE, and RAE, but are not ESS: a 1,1 1,1 1,1 b 1,1 1,1 0,2 c 1,1 2,0 0,0 G 6 In G, the strategy a is not ESS (b can invade), but satisfies all the other properties. 6 4. Summary Table 1 summarizes how the criteria defined in Section 2 and Section 3 are related. A YES in some cell indicates that the criterion mentioned in the corresponding row implies the criterion mentioned in the corresponding column, etc. The bracketed information in the cell indicates which game or definition in this paper, or which other (abbreviated) reference, is relevant for understanding the result. For example, NO [MS] in the NSS/ESS-cell means that neutral stability does not imply evolutionary stability, which is a result due to Maynard-Smith (1982). Acknowledgements I am indebted to Jorgen Weibull who has introduced me to evolutionary game theory and gotten me interested in the topic studied here. I thank a referee for helpful comments, and Handelsbankens forskningsstiftelser for financial support. Table 1 Relationships between different stability criteria ESS NSS REE RAE RIE ESS YES [Def 1] YES [MS] YES [S] YES [Def 5] YES [Def 6] NSS NO [MS] YES [Def 2] NO [W] NO [e.p.g.] NO [e.p.g.] REE NO [S] NO [G ] YES [Def 3] NO [G ] NO [G ] 1 3 3 RAE NO [G ] NO [G ] NO [G ] YES [Def 5] YES [Def 5] 6 1 2 RIE NO [G ] NO [G ] NO [G ] NO [G ] YES [Def 6] 6 1 2 4 YES in a cell indicates that the row criterion implies the column criterion, etc. The bracketed information indicates which game, definition, or other (abbreviated) reference is relevant for the result. e.p.g. means equal payoffs game (any G with A not singleton and u(a,b)5u(c,d) ;a,b,c,d[ A).

50 M. Dufwenberg / Economics Letters 57 (1997) 45 50 References Gans, J.S., 1995. Evolutionary selection of beliefs. Economics Letters 49, 13 17. Maynard-Smith, J., 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge University Press. Maynard-Smith, J., Price, G.R., 1973. The logic of animal conflict. Nature 246, 15 18. Swinkels, J.M., 1992. Evolutionary stability with equilibrium entrants. Journal of Economic Theory 57, 306 332. Weibull, J.W., 1995. Evolutionary Game Theory. MIT Press.