Two extreme views: Managing for Share- or Stakeholders? 1

Similar documents
For Next Time: Read: Responsibility" Whistleblowing" ! Sissela Bok, "Whistleblowing and Professional. ! Richard De Georges, "Whistle Blowing

Business Ethics Journal Review

Chapter 5 CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation. by R. Edward Freeman

Strategic Management and Business Policy, 14e (Wheelen) Chapter 3 Ethics and Social Responsibility in Strategic Management

Business Ethics Concepts & Cases

The philosophy of human. HUMR 5131 Fall 2018, lecture 3 Jakob Elster

CODE OF ETHICS AND CONDUCT OF THE TELECOM ITALIA GROUP

Review of Jason Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

Pluralist test: A situation should be looked at from many different perspectives.!

BBB2154 Business Ethics Prepared by Dr Khairul Anuar. L6 Employment, Discrimination, and Affirmative Action

March 22 was World Water Day. I read some accounts of conferences held around the

Before we look into the operational aspects of firms we need to establish the goals of the firm. This may seem straightforward that firms exist for

Business Ethics Journal Review

Chapter 2 DEFINING BUSINESS ETHICS 1 MGT404 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES

Chapter 5. Ethics in International Business

Purchasing professionals have an ethical responsibility to many groups:

International Business 9e

ETHICS: ORGANISATIONAL CULTURE OR LEADERSHIP

THE MORAL MANAGER: REGAINING ETHICS FOR BUSINESS

Chapter 02 Stakeholder Relationships Social Responsibility and Coroporate Governance

MANAGING SUSTAINABILITY IN MANAGEMENT EDUCATION

Managerial Economics Prof. Trupti Mishra S. J. M. School of Management Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

"Finnair" and "Finnair Group" as used herein refer to Finnair Plc and its subsidiaries.

The grand misapprehension: A response to Aneel Karnani's "'Doing well by doing good': The grand illusion"

MSc. Albina Shabani - Rama CODE OF JUDICIAL ETHICS AS A NECESSARY FACTOR IN IMPROVING PUBLIC S FAITH IN JUSTICE SYSTEM

EMPLOYEE PARTICIPATION IN THE USA: A LEGAL AND MANAGERIAL CONSIDERATION

The social responsibility of corporation and its impact on the reformation of corporate governance structure: a discussion from the perspective of law

Chapter 8: Exchange. 8.1: Introduction. 8.2: Exchange. 8.3: Individual A s Preferences and Endowments

Computer Professionals Responsibilities

Businesses are simply a series of contracts. Consider the following example:

Objectives for Today. The Nature of Ethics. Determinants of Ethics. The Nature of Ethics. Stockholders. Some Failures in Professional Ethics.

ECF2731 Managerial Economics Lecture and Textbook Notes

In 2009, WFP purchased goods and services. breach of ethics at a minimum affects WFP. Impropriety can affect WFP s ability to achieve its mandate.

BPK5B Corporate Ethics and Governance. Unit : I - V

HONESTY IN THE WORKPLACE 1. The Importance and Implementation of. Honesty in the Workplace. Sadie B. Dixon. Southern Adventist University

Ethics and Business Conduct

1. What do you understand by social responsibility of business? How is it different from legal responsibility?

1. Business ethics involves the application of standards of moral behavior to business situations.

Wilo Group Code of Conduct. "Responsible Behaviour

CODE OF CONDUCT. Securing What Matters

Business Ethics Journal Review

COURT OF JUSTICE OF THE EUROPEAN UNION CASE C-621/18 WIGHTMAN

Paper 3 - Fundamentals of Laws and Ethics

Relevant Costs and Revenues

Anglo-Saxon (Shareholder) Continental (Stakeholder) Considers not only the interest of shareholders but other stakeholders too. profit orientation

B100 Day School Three Blocks 6 and 7. Your Tutor: Chris Green

Business Assessment. Advisor Tool Galliard, Inc. All Rights Reserved

The Company seeks to comply with both the letter and spirit of the laws and regulations in all jurisdictions in which it operates.

Code of business conduct

EVROSTON ECONOMICS AND MANAGEMENT CONSULTANTS CORPORATE BUSINESS ETHICS POLICY

CODE OF CONDUCT. of the Greiner Group

THE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY OF CORPORATIONS AND HOW TO MAKE IT WORK FOR YOU. by John Hasnas *

CODE OF BUSINESS CONDUCT

LEARNING OBJECTIVES CORPORATE RESPONSIBILITY. Session 5. Corporate social responsibility and corporate governance

LexisNexis Academic. Copyright 1999 The Financial Times Limited Financial Times (London,England) December 13, 1999, Monday Surveys MST1

Chapter 002 Defining Business Ethics

Test Bank for Business Ethics Now 3rd Edition by Ghillyer

Supplimentary material for Research at the Auction Block: Problems for the Fair Benefits Approach to International Research

Test Bank for Business Ethics Now 3rd Edition by Ghillyer

Public Internal Control Systems in the European Union

CORPORATE GOVERNANCE: THE STAKEHOLDERS PERSPECTIVE

California employers are burdened with more wage and hour gotchas than any other

Commission of the European Communities v United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland

Results and Retention

Session on International Enforcement Perspectives Federal Trade Commission and Antitrust Division Hearings on Section 2 of the Sherman Act

Introduction to Moral Issues: Homework 2

CORPORATE ETHICS AND SHAREHOLDER WEALTH MAXIMIZATION

Chapter 2 Stakeholder Relationships, Social Responsibility, and Corporate Governance

Department of Industrial Engineering. Chapter 4 Organizing And Staffing The Project Office And Team

Chapter Three British Parliamentary Debate as a Model of Educational and Social Debate

Page: Page 1 of 5 Effective Date: January 27, 2004 Authorized By: President and CEO Function: Executive

Link download full of Test Bank for Business Ethics Now 3rd Edition by Ghillyer. Click here

Engineering Ethics: Case Studies

Ratos AB Adopted by Ratos s Board on February 2018 (replaces previous version adopted 16 February 2017)

CONTENTS. 03 Introduction. 04 The Code. 07 Compliance with the Code. 08 Who to Contact. 08 Whistleblowing policy. -Ensuring we do not act corruptly

APPEARANCES PRELIMINARY STATEMENT. The undersigned was appointed to arbitrate a dispute between the United

When making decisions affecting Long Island University s assets and/or resources, individuals must adhere to the following standards:

Ethics and the Conduct of Business

Sustainability. Plan for the United States

Rebates: Formalism, Effects and the Real World

4/29/2014. OPERATIONALIZING ETHICS IN BUSINESS SETTINGS Case Example: Less Sugar Marketing

LEVEL 3 - UNIT 6 - EMPLOYMENT LAW SUGGESTED ANSWERS - JUNE 2013

Ethics. Corporate Principles. Code of Conduct. 1 General Principles

1.4 Stakeholders. Stakeholders - Owners. - Government - Consumer - Customer - Environment - Community - Shareholders - Employees - Suppliers.

Bahrain Seminar on Accounting and Auditing Standards

Spontaneous Cooperation under Anarchy

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: FALL 2008

Realizing. Issue 17 LEADERSHIP. Everyday Leaders Changing Our World. Linda Fisher Thornton in Conversation ETHICAL LEADERSHIP

Group Code of Ethics

Title: Business Ethics Professor: Ken Butterfield. online.wsu.edu

SUGGESTED SOLUTIONS TOP CA CASE STUDY EXAMINATION. All Rights Reserved

Scottish Rugby Marketing Guide for Clubs

CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY: MYTH OR REALITY?

Job Applicant Privacy Notice

BUSINESS ETHICS AND CORPORATE GOVERNANCE TERMINOLOGY AND CONCEPTS

Commentary: Causes of Changing Earnings Inequality

The hypothetical world with which the concept of perfect competition is concerned is one in which markets have the following characteristics:

MANAGERIAL MODELS OF THE FIRM

Business and society. 93% of CEOs believe that sustainability issues will be critical to the future success of their business

Transcription:

Two extreme views: Managing for Share- or Stakeholders? 1 Julian Fink julian.fink@uni- bayreuth.de (1) Another sceptical challenge? Consider first a misguided sceptical argument against business ethics. Suppose Jack says that managers are subject to ethical obligations. There are things they ought to and ought not to do. Jill challenges Jack in asking the following: So managers are subject to ethical obligations. What precisely are they? What is it that managers ought and ought not to do? Suppose Jack replies: I don t really know what it is precisely that managers ought to do. However, I know that they ought and ought not to do something. Can Jill then legitimately challenge Jack s position by charging him with inconsistency? That is, is Jack inconsistent in asserting that there are moral obligations without having a determined view about what they are? (2) Share- vs. stakeholder ethics (2.1) Friedman s view: ethics = constraint profit maximisation (2.1.1) In Capitalism and Freedom, Milton Freeman makes the following remark. Consider a society based on private property rights. In such a society, Friedman claims, there is one and only one social responsibility of business to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game, which is to say, engages in open and free competition, without deception or fraud. Few trends could so undermine the very foundations of our free society as the acceptance by corporate officials of a social responsibility other than to make as much money for their stockholders as possible. 2 What is the precise view Friedman defends here? First, Friedman speaks about social responsibility. It is safe to translate this into a moral view, i.e., a view about what is morally permissible, or what ought to be case from the moral point of view. Second, he talks about corporate officials (aka corporate officers ), i.e. the highest raking officials with executive powers, commonly knows as managers. Third, Friedman (loosely) talks about rules of the game ; let s think of this as the law. 1 This lecture is primarily based on chap. 2 of Sanbu s Just Business: Arguments in Business Ethics. 2 Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom, 1983: 133. 1

Given these clarifications, let s characterise Friedman s view a bit further. Note first that Friedman s view is perhaps surprisingly neither an expression of amoralism nor of moral scepticism. Friedman does not deny objective morality. Nor does he tell us to be indifferent towards moral considerations. Quite the contrary: Friedman s view is in fact a deeply moral one. Managers have a moral obligation. Their obligation is to manage corporations profitably. Furthermore: Friedman does not say that managers ought to be egoistic (i.e. maximise their own benefits). Nor should managers do whatever they want. Again, his view is that it is not only permissible to manage businesses solely to maximise profits; it is morally required to do so (Sandbu, p. 17). Second, though Friedman emphasises increasing profit as what is morally required, there is a more fundamental consideration behind his view. Consider this quote: A group of person may establish a corporation for a purpose for example, a hospital or a school. The manager of such a corporation will not have money profit as his objective but the rendering of certain services the key point is the manager is the agent of the individuals who own the corporation or establish the eleemosynary institution, and his primary responsibility is to them. 3 Consequently, the manager s obligation is not to maximise profits per se. Instead, managers are under the obligation to fulfil the shareholders interests and desires. A correct name for Friedman s view would thus be shareholder primacy; an attempt of rendering his view precise could read as follows: Friedman s shareholder-primacy view. For all acts A, if A is an act of a manger M qua manager, then M is morally required to A if and only if (i) A is instrumental to fulfilling the desires of the M s shareholders and (ii) the fact that M does A is not illegal. How could one justify this shareholder- primacy view? Three strategies seem possible. One is to emphasise the social role of managers. What matters for the moral evaluation of a manager is the aim of a managerial position. Put simply, the aim of a managerial position is to serve the owners of the corporation and to fulfil their interests. This aim of the manger s social role entails the shareholder- primacy view, or so one may argue. The second possible defence stems from consequentialism. Suppose consequentialism says, roughly, that whether you ought or ought not to perform an act A depends solely on A s consequences. It does therefore not 3 Friedman, The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits, 1970. 2

depend on intrinsic features of A. Suppose this is correct. Imagine that a manager leaves the path of profit maximising. For example: he or she refrains from firing unproductive employees for the sake of keeping unemployment low. But suppose, as a consequence, this would hurt, rather than improve societies well- being by, for instance, diminishing technological innovation and limiting the growth of productivity. Let us assume this harms society more than what is gained through the prevention of unemployment. Then it would not be right from a consequentialist perspective to keep unproductive employees employed and to leave the path of profit maximisation. So, in general, the consequentialist defence of the shareholder supremacy view can be expressed as follows. Suppose that the public good and well- being is promoted more effectively if managers in fact ignore social responsibility and moral concerns and concentrate on maximising profits. Given the correctness of consequentialism, this explains why a manager in fact satisfies a moral obligation by focusing on profit maximisation. But surely, this defence is sound only if (i) the public good and well being is in fact promoted by profit- maximising behaviour and (ii) if moral obligation is portrayed correctly in consequentalist terms. The third justification of Friedman s shareholder- primacy view is a rights- based one. Consider the view upon which an act is morally impermissible if it violates a legitimate right of a person. No doubt, as the owners of corporations, shareholders have certain property rights: they are entitled to use, transfer, and generate income from their property. Consequently, one may argue, that these rights may give rise to the mangers duty to act in the shareholders interests. Here is how to construct the argument. First, the owners (shareholders) invest their assets into a company for a certain purpose. Let us assume they do so in order to create interest and dividends, i.e. to generate profit. Then managers are hired by the owners to handle (i.e. manage) their investment and to execute the shareholders interests. Consequently, a manger would infringe a right of the shareholders at least partly if they were to act against the shareholders interests; it is simply not their money. It is morally wrong to use other people s money for purposes not in accordance with their will. Thus expressed radically engaging in corporate social responsibility when not increasing profits thus infringes a right, in an immoral fashion, resembling theft, in fact. Compare an analogous argument concerning promising (cf. Sanbu, p. 19). (2.1.2) However, upon reflection, it seems that Friedman s pure shareholder- primacy view must be rejected. It seems untenable to think that a manager is morally required to do whatever his principal and shareholder wants. Compare a Mafia boss, for instance, who owns a company and wants his competitors to be eliminated (physically). This does not seem to generate an obligation for the agents of that company to fulfil this wish. Consequently, to give us a plausible account of ethics, the shareholder- primacy view needs to be qualified. There 3

need to be some ethical constraint that exists independently of shareholder interests. Friedman himself admits a qualification: The managers responsibility is to conduct the business in accordance with [shareholders ] desires, which generally will be to make as much money as possible while conforming to the basic rules of society, both those embodied in law and those embodied in ethical custom. However, this remark seems to make Friedman s view circular. Roughly, it now says that a manager is morally permitted to A if and only if (i) A-ing serves the shareholders interests and (ii) A is morally permitted. This is a circular view; it cannot inform us what managers are morally permitted or required to do. (2.2) From share- to stakeholders ethics (2.2.1) Shareholder primacy says that business should be managed to benefit shareholders. The stakeholders view says that businesses should be managed to benefit stakeholders. But who are stakeholders? Defined generally, a stakeholder is an individual (or a group) who are factually or potentially affected by the activities of a corporation. In a real world scenario, who are they? Consider an incomplete list: shareholders (investors), employees, customers, suppliers, unions, the government, communities etc. Here is the essence of the stakeholder approach in R. Edward Freeman s words, a major proponent of this view. Corporations shall be managed in the interests of its stakeholders, defined as employees, financier, customers, employees [sic], and communities. 4 In consequence, the stakeholder approach does not, prima facie, give priority to a particular group of stakeholders (i.e. shareholders). Instead, ethical management consists in management keeping the relationships and the benefits for the diversity of stakeholders in balance. How can this view be defended? And why is it supposed to be more plausible than shareholder primacy? Recall the right- based defence of the shareholder- primacy view. Shareholders have a right to ensure that their managers act in their interests. This right stems as suggested before from the agent- principal relationship between managers and shareholders. Shareholders employ their managers as their agents, thereby creating formal informal contracts. These contractual relations give rise to the managers obligation to maximise profits. 4 Freeman, A Stakeholder Theory of Modern Corporation. 4

Consequently, shares distribute rights and obligations among shareholders and managers. But cannot the same be said for stakes? Take a local community who permits a business to operate in their vicinity, i.e. to built factories, streets, and other facilities. In part, the community will be affected negatively by the operation. This gives rise to a right of compensation: for instance, the local community has rights to benefit from the companies operation and to expect that the newly established business will behave like good corporate citizen (consider the analogy of the legitimate expectations a community could have towards a natural person joining a community). The community has a right to not to be exposed to uncontrollable hazards like toxic pollution or exploitation of local workforce. Freeman, for instance, goes as far as saying that [w]hen the firm mismanages its relationship with the local community, it is in the same position as a citizen who commits a crime. It has violated the implicit social contract with the community and should expect to be distrusted and ostracized. It should not be surprised if punitive measures are invoked. 5 Surely, a similar rights- based view could explain the special duties of management towards customers and employees etc. (2.2.2) Is the stakeholder approach a plausible alternative to the shareholder- primacy view? Perhaps it appears plausible at first sight. Corporations should not only benefit an already privileged group in society (i.e. owners or capital means, investors). However, the stakeholder approach also faces a variety of problems. First, consider the identification problem. Who belongs to the group of a company s stakeholders? all potentially affected? Then this definition stretches very far. It may include the media, Greenpeace etc? To act ethically, does a manager really have manage in the interests of these groups? Second, what precisely does it mean to manage in the interests of stakeholders? Obviously, the different groups have different interests. Suppose stakeholder theory is saying that mangers should maximise the benefits to all stakeholder groups (much as shareholder primacy says that maximize the shareholder s interests). However, this view leads to impossible imperatives, as one cannot maximise more than one objective simultaneously. Similarity, suppose we conceive of managers as agents of stakeholders as their principals, and this relationship creates duties for managers. No doubt, this would mean that managers face an array of conflicting duties; i.e. duties that they cannot fulfil simultaneously. Contemporary stakeholder theory does not say much as to how to resolve these conflicts. 5 Ibid. 5

How could one defend the stakeholder view? In other words, why do stakeholders matter morally when it comes to ethical management? Two general strategies seem possible: (i) managing in the interest of multiple stakeholders is the best means to achieve something else, e.g. profit maximisation. If this is correct, business should be managed in the interest of stakeholders for instrumental moral reasons. Alternatively, perhaps there is an argument that (ii) managing in the interest of stakeholders is right for the sake of the stakeholders (i.e. for intrinsic moral reasons). 6