Homo moralis. preference evolution under incomplete information and assortative matching

Similar documents
Markets and Values. The Evolution of Intrinsic Motivation. Tim Besley and Maitreesh Ghatak. November 2015

How Exposure to Markets Can Favor Inequity-Averse Preferences y

Norm Compliance and Strong Reciprocity

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance. How selfish are people?

MERITOCRACY AS A MECHANISM IN THE CONTEXT OF VOLUNTARY CONTRIBUTION GAMES

BEEM109 Experimental Economics and Finance. How selfish are people?

Sustaining Cooperation in Social Exchange Networks with Incomplete Global Information

Intergenerational Mobility in Theory

On the relation between guessing games and bidding in auctions

Selling with Evidence

The Role of Cultural Leaders in the Transmission of Preferences

Just Luck: An Experimental Study of Risk Taking and Fairness Webappendix, not to be published.

Relative profit maximization and Bertrand equilibrium with quadratic cost functions

Industrial Organization 04

Matching Markets with Endogenous Information

Summer 2003 (420 2)

Symmetric Information Benchmark Begin by setting up a comparison situation, where there is no information asymmetry. Notation:

Modeling Altruism and Spitefulness in Experiments 1

Assortative Matching > 0. (2)

An Alternative to Signaling: Directed Search and Substitution

Market Forces meet Behavioral Biases

EXTERNALITIES AND PRICING ON MULTIDIMENSIONAL. MATCHING PLATFORMS: Online Appendix

Strategic Ignorance in the Second-Price Auction

Some references by topic

Bargaining, power and the net neutrality problem

Supplimentary material for Research at the Auction Block: Problems for the Fair Benefits Approach to International Research

STABILITY AND WELFARE OF MERITOCRATIC GROUP-BASED MECHANISMS

The Microfoundations of Urban Agglomeration Economies: Dicussion of Duranton and Puga (DP), 2004

An Introduction to Game Theory

Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements

Buyer Heterogeneity and Dynamic Sorting in Markets for Durable Lemons

Field Exam January Labor Economics PLEASE WRITE YOUR ANSWERS FOR EACH PART IN A SEPARATE BOOK.

Economics 101A (Lecture 27) Stefano DellaVigna

Chapter 2 Social Group Utility Maximization Framework

The Core Pareto Optimality and Social Welfare Maximizationty

Lab 2: Mathematical Modeling: Hardy-Weinberg 1. Overview. In this lab you will:

Labor Economics, Lectures 3 and 4: Social Mobility, Peer Effects and Human Capital

The Role of Price Floor in a Differentiated Product Retail Market 1

Game Theory & Firms. Jacob LaRiviere & Justin Rao April 20, 2016 Econ 404, Spring 2016

EVOLUTION OF POPULATIONS Genes and Variation

SOCIAL PUNISHMENT. October 5, 2005

Leadership and Information

Simple Market Equilibria with Rationally Inattentive Consumers

Title: Responsibility-Alleviation and Other-Regarding Preferences with Peer Workers in Labor

Price of anarchy in auctions & the smoothness framework. Faidra Monachou Algorithmic Game Theory 2016 CoReLab, NTUA

Socially Optimal Altruism in a Game of Sequential Punishment

ECONS 424 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY MIDTERM EXAM #2

Asset Price Bubbles and Endogenous Growth [PRELIMINARY DRAFT] Abstract

Learning by Observing

Co-evolution of strategies and update rules in the prisoner s dilemma game on complex networks

Money and Credit with Limited Commitment and Theft

Introduction to Artificial Intelligence. Prof. Inkyu Moon Dept. of Robotics Engineering, DGIST

POPULATION GENETICS. Evolution Lectures 4

Wireless Networking with Selfish Agents. Li (Erran) Li Center for Networking Research Bell Labs, Lucent Technologies

Part IV. Pricing strategies and market segmentation

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

ECON 500 Microeconomic Theory MARKET FAILURES. Asymmetric Information Externalities Public Goods

Imperfect Competition Among Liquidity Providers

First-Price Auctions with General Information Structures: A Short Introduction

Uniform and Targeted Advertising with Shoppers and. Asymmetric Loyal Market Shares

Reputation and Performance

Topics in ALGORITHMIC GAME THEORY *

1.. There are two complementary goods that are consumed together (each individual good

Dynamic Pricing in Experience Good Markets with Demand Uncertainty

Reciprocity versus Reelection: Theory and Experiment

DIVERSE ORGANIZATIONS

14.27 Economics and E-Commerce Fall 14. Lecture 2 - Review

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory

Appendix to Skill-Biased Technical Change, Educational Choice, and Labor Market Polarization: The U.S. versus Europe

The Wisdom of Networked and Evolving Agents

UNIK Multiagent systems Lecture 5. Non-cooperative game theory. Jonas Moen

Some relationships between evolutionary stability criteria in games

Credence goods. Even when the success of the service is observable to the consumer ex post, consumers typically

Bidding Clubs in First-Price Auctions Extended Abstract

Modeling of competition in revenue management Petr Fiala 1

Entry decisions and bidding behavior in sequential first-price procurement auctions: An experimental study

Theory Appendix. 1 Model Setup

EXAMINATION #4 VERSION C General Equilibrium and Market Power November 24, 2015

Characterization of the Support of the Mixed. Strategy Price Equilibria in Oligopolies with. Heterogeneous Consumers

The Robust Price of Anarchy of Altruistic Games

Applied Microeconometrics I

11.1 Genetic Variation Within Population. KEY CONCEPT A population shares a common gene pool.

IO Field Examination Department of Economics, Michigan State University May 17, 2004

Harvard University Department of Economics

EXERCISE 1. Testing Hardy-Weinberg Equilibrium. 1a. Fill in Table 1. Calculate the initial genotype and allele frequencies.

Department of Economics. Discussion Paper Series

Section KEY CONCEPT A population shares a common gene pool.

Volume 30, Issue 3. Specialization through Cross-licensing in a Multi-product Stackelberg Duopoly

University of California, Davis Date: June 24, PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE. Answer four questions (out of five)

Luca Spataro Lectures 2. Public Economics. Efficiency (Ref. Myles 1995, ch. 2) March 2015, University of Pisa

Advance Selling, Competition, and Brand Substitutability

A Heuristic Bidding Strategy for Multiple Heterogeneous Auctions

Do Social Preferences Matter in Competitive Markets?

Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only. Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use.

Bertrand colludes more than Cournot

14.03 Exam 3 Fall 2000 DO NOT OPEN THIS EXAM UNTIL TIME IS ANNOUNCED!

Econ Microeconomic Analysis and Policy

Rationing Poor Consumers to Reduce Prices

Psychology and Economics Field Exam August 2015

Transcription:

Homo moralis preference evolution under incomplete information and assortative matching Ingela Alger (TSE, LERNA, CNRS, IAST, and Carleton University) Jörgen W. Weibull (Stockholm School of Economics and IAST) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 1 / 40

Introduction Economists traditionally assume selfishness I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 2 / 40

Introduction Economists traditionally assume selfishness However, sometimes social or other-regarding preferences are assumed: altruism (Becker), warm glow (Andreoni), inequity aversion (Fehr and Schmidt), preference for effi ciency (Charness and Rabin), reciprocal altruism (Levine), esteem (Bénabou and Tirole) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 2 / 40

Introduction Economists traditionally assume selfishness However, sometimes social or other-regarding preferences are assumed: altruism (Becker), warm glow (Andreoni), inequity aversion (Fehr and Schmidt), preference for effi ciency (Charness and Rabin), reciprocal altruism (Levine), esteem (Bénabou and Tirole) Some classical economists included moral values in human motivation, see Smith (1759) and Edgeworth (1881) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 2 / 40

Introduction Economists traditionally assume selfishness However, sometimes social or other-regarding preferences are assumed: altruism (Becker), warm glow (Andreoni), inequity aversion (Fehr and Schmidt), preference for effi ciency (Charness and Rabin), reciprocal altruism (Levine), esteem (Bénabou and Tirole) Some classical economists included moral values in human motivation, see Smith (1759) and Edgeworth (1881) see also Arrow (1973), Laffont (1975), Sen (1977), Tabellini (2008) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 2 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? Study evolutionary foundations of human motivation! I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? Study evolutionary foundations of human motivation! all our ancestors were successful at reproducing I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? Study evolutionary foundations of human motivation! all our ancestors were successful at reproducing suppose that we have inherited our ancestors preferences (genetically, epigenetically, culturally) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? Study evolutionary foundations of human motivation! all our ancestors were successful at reproducing suppose that we have inherited our ancestors preferences (genetically, epigenetically, culturally) then our preferences should direct us towards maximization of reproductive success I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction What preferences and/or moral values should we expect humans to have, from first principles? Study evolutionary foundations of human motivation! all our ancestors were successful at reproducing suppose that we have inherited our ancestors preferences (genetically, epigenetically, culturally) then our preferences should direct us towards maximization of reproductive success...but theory suggests that this need not be the case! I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 3 / 40

Introduction Evolution of preferences in decision problems Counter-mechanism: imperfect perception and response systems Research by: Gary Becker Luis Rayo Arthur Robson Larry Samuelson I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 4 / 40

Introduction Preference evolution in strategic interactions Under complete information: Counter-mechanism: commitment value of preferences Example: the responder in an ultimatum game benefits from being known to be inequity averse Research: Bester & Güth (1998) Bolle (2000) Possajennikov (2000) Koçkesen, Ok & Sethi (2000) Sethi & Somanathan (2001) Heifetz, Shannon and Spiegel (2007) Alger & Weibull (2010, 2012), Alger (2010) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 5 / 40

Introduction Preference evolution in strategic interactions Under incomplete information: preferences have no strategic commitment value: natural selection leads to preferences that maximize individual reproductive success homo oeconomicus prevails! Research: Ok & Vega-Redondo (2001) Dekel, Ely & Yilankaya (2007) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 6 / 40

Introduction Today s paper: preference evolution in strategic interactions under incomplete information I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 7 / 40

Introduction Today s paper: preference evolution in strategic interactions under incomplete information We impose few restrictions and yet... I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 7 / 40

Introduction Today s paper: preference evolution in strategic interactions under incomplete information We impose few restrictions and yet... The math leads to a general class of moral preferences: homo moralis I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 7 / 40

Introduction Today s paper: preference evolution in strategic interactions under incomplete information We impose few restrictions and yet... The math leads to a general class of moral preferences: homo moralis A homo moralis gives some weight to own reproductive success and some weight to what is the right thing to do. Torn between - selfishness and - morality in line with Immanuel Kant s categorical imperative I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 7 / 40

Introduction Kant s categorical imperative Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 8 / 40

Introduction Driving force: assortativity in the matching process Hamilton (1964), Hines and Maynard Smith (1979), Grafen (1979, 2006), Bergstrom (1995, 2003, 2009), Rousset (2004) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 9 / 40

Outline Model Results Three points: assortativity is common the behavior of homo moralis is compatible with experimental evidence morality is different from altruism Conclusion I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 10 / 40

Model A large (continuum) population Individuals are randomly matched into pairs Each pair has a symmetric interaction, with strategy set X π (x, y): fitness increment from using strategy x X against y X I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 11 / 40

Model Each individual has a type θ, which defines a goal function u θ : X 2 R Type set: Θ u θ is continuous ( θ Θ) Homo oeconomicus: u = π Each individual s type is his/her private information I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 12 / 40

Model At most two types present, θ and τ, in proportions 1 ε and ε If ε is small, θ is the resident type and τ the mutant type Pr [θ τ, ε]: conditional match probability Pr [θ τ, ε] is continuous in ε Write σ for lim ε 0 Pr [τ τ, ε]; the index of assortativity of the matching process (Bergstrom, 2003) Uniform random matching σ = 0 Interactions between siblings who inherited their types from their common parents σ = 1/2 I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 13 / 40

Model Definition A strategy pair (x, y ) is a (Bayesian) Nash Equilibrium (BNE) in state s = (θ, τ, ε) if { x arg max x X Pr [θ θ, ε] u θ (x, x ) + Pr [τ θ, ε] u θ (x, y ) y arg max y X Pr [θ τ, ε] u τ (y, x ) + Pr [τ τ, ε] u τ (y, y ). I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 14 / 40

Model Average fitnesses in state s = (θ, τ, ε) at strategy profile (x, y ): Π θ (x, y, ε) = Pr [θ θ, ε] π (x, x ) + Pr [τ θ, ε] π (x, y ) Π τ (x, y, ε) = Pr [θ τ, ε] π (y, x ) + Pr [τ τ, ε] π (y, y ) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 15 / 40

Model Definition A type θ Θ is evolutionarily stable against a type τ Θ if there exists an ε > 0 such that Π θ (x, y, ε) > Π τ (x, y, ε) in all Nash equilibria (x, y ) in all states s = (θ, τ, ε) with ε (0, ε). I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 16 / 40

Model Definition A type θ Θ is evolutionarily unstable if there exists a type τ Θ such that for each ε > 0 there exists an ε (0, ε) with Π θ (x, y, ε) < Π τ (x, y, ε) in all Nash equilibria (x, y ) in state s = (θ, τ, ε). I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 17 / 40

Results Definition An individual is a homo moralis with degree of morality κ [0, 1] if her utility function is of the form u κ (x, y) = (1 κ) π (x, y) + κ π (x, x) Homo moralis is torn between selfishness and morality: - π (x, y): maximizing own fitness - π (x, x): doing what would be right for both, in terms of fitness, if the other party did the same I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 18 / 40

Results Definition A homo hamiltoniensis (a homage to the late evolutionary biologist William Hamilton) is a homo moralis with degree of morality κ = σ: u σ (x, y) = (1 σ) π (x, y) + σ π (x, x) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 19 / 40

Results Let What HH does when resident: β σ (y) = arg max x X u σ (x, y) X σ = {x X : x β σ (x)} Θ m σ : set of types τ that, as vanishingly rare mutants, when residents play some x σ X σ, also play x σ I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 20 / 40

Results Theorem (Part 1) If β σ (x) is a singleton for all x X σ, then homo hamiltoniensis is evolutionarily stable against all types τ / Θ m σ. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 21 / 40

Results Intuition: HH preempts mutants I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 22 / 40

Results Intuition: HH preempts mutants A resident population of HH play some x σ : x σ arg max x X (1 σ) π (x, x σ) + σ π (x, x) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 22 / 40

Results Intuition: HH preempts mutants A resident population of HH play some x σ : x σ arg max x X (1 σ) π (x, x σ) + σ π (x, x) A vanishingly rare mutant type, who plays some z X, obtains average fitness (1 σ) π (z, x σ ) + σ π (z, z) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 22 / 40

Results The type space Θ is rich if for every strategy x X there exists a type for which x is strictly dominant. Theorem (Part 2) If Θ is rich, X θ X σ = and X θ is a singleton, then θ is evolutionarily unstable. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 23 / 40

Results Intuition Consider any resident type θ who plays some x θ where x θ / X σ I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 24 / 40

Results Intuition Consider any resident type θ who plays some x θ where x θ / X σ Θ rich type ˆτ committed to a best reply ˆx to x θ in terms of average mutant fitness (in the limit as ε = 0) ˆx arg max x X (1 σ) π (x, x θ) + σ π (x, x) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 24 / 40

Results Homo oeconomicus thrives in non-strategic environments (decision problems) I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 25 / 40

Results Homo oeconomicus thrives in non-strategic environments (decision problems) For homo oeconomicus to thrive in strategic interactions, it is necessary that the index of assortativity be zero. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 25 / 40

Matching processes Assortativity is positive as soon as there is a positive probability that both parties in an interaction have inherited their preferences (or moral values) from a common ancestor (genetic or cultural) A long tradition in biology... In social science: culture, education, ethnicity, geography, networks, customs and habits I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 26 / 40

Matching processes Interactions between kin: vertical transmission Pairwise interactions between siblings, for which strategies are not gender specific A population of grown-ups where a proportion 1 ε have type θ Θ and the residual proportion has strategy τ Θ Suppose that couples form randomly Assume that each child is equally likely to inherit each parent s type I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 27 / 40

Matching processes Interactions between kin: vertical transmission Proposition Under random mating and monogamy, σ = 1/2. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 28 / 40

Matching processes Interactions between kin: oblique transmission Proposition Assume monogamy, and suppose that each child inherits: a parent s type with probability ρ [0, 1] the type of a uniformly randomly drawn grown-up in the population otherwise the siblings choices of role model are statistically independent. Then σ = ρ 2 /2. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 29 / 40

Matching processes Interactions between non-kin: education Proposition Each individual: acquires her business strategies in school enters a new two-person business partnership upon finishing school: with a former schoolmate with probability υ [0, 1], with a graduate uniformly randomly drawn from the whole pool of newly minted graduates in society at large otherwise. Then σ = υ. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 30 / 40

Matching processes Interactions between non-kin: migration Proposition A hunter gatherer society in which each community has a hunting team consisting of two men. Hunting techniques taught to youngsters. A fraction γ [0, 1] of the young men migrate from their native community to a uniformly randomly drawn community in society at large, while the others remain in their native community. Then σ = 1 γ. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 31 / 40

Homo moralis in action: dictator game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the dictator, with equal probability for both I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 32 / 40

Homo moralis in action: dictator game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the dictator, with equal probability for both The dictator decides, unilaterally, how to split the money I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 32 / 40

Homo moralis in action: dictator game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the dictator, with equal probability for both The dictator decides, unilaterally, how to split the money A strategy x [0, 1] is the share to give, if dictator, to the other party π (x, y) = 1 [v (1 x) + v (y)] 2 I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 32 / 40

Homo moralis in action: dictator game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the dictator, with equal probability for both The dictator decides, unilaterally, how to split the money A strategy x [0, 1] is the share to give, if dictator, to the other party π (x, y) = 1 [v (1 x) + v (y)] 2 Homo moralis gives a positive amount to the other if κ is large enough I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 32 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the proposer, with equal probability for both I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 33 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the proposer, with equal probability for both The proposer suggests a split. The other party, the responder, may reject, and then all money is lost. I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 33 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game Two individuals. Hand money to one of the two, the proposer, with equal probability for both The proposer suggests a split. The other party, the responder, may reject, and then all money is lost. A strategy x = (x 1, x 2 ) [0, 1] 2 is - the share to suggest if proposer, x 1 - the acceptance threshold if responder, x 2 π (x, y) = 1 2 v (1 x 1) 1 {x1 y 2 } + 1 2 v (y 1) 1 {y1 x 2 } I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 33 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game x2 1.0 0.5 0.5 1.0 x1 Equilibrium strategies when σ = 0 I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 34 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game x2 1.0 0.5 0.5 1.0 x1 Equilibrium strategies when σ = 1/4 I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 35 / 40

Homo moralis in action: ultimatum game x2 1.0 0.5 0.5 1.0 x1 Equilibrium strategies when σ = 1 I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 36 / 40

Morality vs. altruism Altruist: u α (x, y) = π (x, y) + α π (y, x), for some degree of altruism α [0, 1] Homo moralis: u κ (x, y) = (1 κ) π (x, y) + κ π (x, x) for some degree of of morality κ [0, 1] I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 37 / 40

Morality vs. altruism x 1.5 1.0 0.5 0.0 0.0 0.5 1.0 1.5 Best-reply curves in a public-goods game y I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 38 / 40

Conclusion Homo oeconomicus thrives in: decision problems under uniform random matching In all other situations: natural selection wipes out homo oeconomicus and instead favors homo moralis the resulting degree of morality is determined by the assortativity in the matching process I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 39 / 40

Conclusion Avenues for further research: interactions between n > 2 individuals heterogeneity partial information population processes and stochastic stability implications for political economy & public finance I. Alger &. J.W. Weibull () Homo moralis 40 / 40