Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only. Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use.

Similar documents
Analyzing Choice with Revealed Preference: Is Altruism Rational?

Summer 2003 (420 2)

GARP for Kids: On the Development of Rational Choice Behavior

Revealing Preferences Graphically: An Old Method Gets a New Tool Kit

Chapter 1: Preferences and Utility. Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Farm Level Nonparametric Analysis of Profit Maximization Behavior with Measurement Error

Cambridge University Press Modeling Monetary Economies, Second Edition - Bruce Champ and Scott Freeman Excerpt More information.

Critical Investigations to Revealed Preference Theory

Chapter 3 Outline. Consumer Theory. Chapter 3: Model of Consumer Behavior. Challenge: Why Americans Buy E-Books and Germans Do Not

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 7

Student Guide to Intermediate Microeconomics: An Interactive Approach

Introduction 3. For general queries, contact

Chapter 10 Consumer Choice and Behavioral Economics

Notes and Comments on Search Costs and. Equilibrium Price Dispersion. Moshe Barach. Based on Information, Search and Price Dispersion

Tristan Blümli. Abstract:

The 2x2 Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/2 (Lecture 8, Micro Theory I)

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

Existence of a Pareto optimal social interaction outcome with non-binary preferences

Farm-level nonparametric analysis of cost-minimization and profit-maximization behavior

Efficiency in Second-Price Auctions: A New Look at Old Data

EconS Bertrand Competition

Web appendix to: A note on different approaches to index number theory

LECTURE NOTE 2 PREFERENCES

The 2x2 Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2012/11/21 (Lecture 2, Micro Theory I)

Supplimentary material for Research at the Auction Block: Problems for the Fair Benefits Approach to International Research

Lecture 1: Preference Relations and Utility Functions

Chapter 1- Introduction

Econ 303. Weeks 3-4 Consumer Theory

Econ 2310 Midterm, Winter hours, YOU MUST HAND IN THE EXAM. Section A. Each Question is worth 5 marks

January Examinations 2015

Introduction. Consumer Choice 20/09/2017

University of California, Davis Date: June 24, PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE. Answer four questions (out of five)

James Swofford, Lena Birkelöf, John Filer. A Smaller Step: Tests of Microeconomic Foundation of a Scandinavian Common Currency Area

Notes on Intertemporal Consumption Choice

Final Exam - Solutions

Criticism of Indifference Curve Theory

MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS 2: SPE, UNCOVERED SET, BANKS SET

1 Competitive Equilibrium

LECTURE NOTE 2 UTILITY

Economics for Business. Lecture 1- The Market Forces of Supply and Demand

Microeconomics I - Outline

Time Inconsistency or Inconsistency?

A Note on The Simple Analytics of the Environmental Kuznets Curve

Econ Microeconomics Notes

Topic Compensating Differentials. Professor H.J. Schuetze Economics 370

Oligopoly: How do firms behave when there are only a few competitors? These firms produce all or most of their industry s output.

Producer Theory - Monopoly

Quasi linear Utility and Two Market Monopoly

Economics and Cost benefit analysis for climate changes: an introduction, part II

A COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM WITH PRODUCT DIFFERENTIATION

1.6 Duality, Integrability & Revealed Preference

LECTURE NOTES. HCS 112 Fundamentals of economics INTRODUCTION. After completing this part, students should be able to:

Ch. 1 LECTURE NOTES Learning objectives II. Definition of Economics III. The Economic Perspective CONSIDER THIS Free for All?

Economics 323 Microeconomic Theory Fall 2016

MICRO-ECONOMIC THEORY I STUDY NOTES CHAPTER ONE

International Economics Twelfth Edition

File: ch01, Chapter 1: Analyzing Economic Problems. Multiple Choice

Economics 335 Price Discrimination Answer Key. (a) (page 1) You have to show with the aid of graphs that the monopolist s total demand is given by

Experimental Test of the Giffen Good

The Efficient Allocation of Individuals to Positions

Using this information, we then write the output of a firm as

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

FIRST FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF WELFARE ECONOMICS

Ecn Intermediate Microeconomic Theory University of California - Davis December 10, 2009 Instructor: John Parman. Final Exam

Do not open this exam until told to do so. Solution

Section 1: Neoclassical welfare economics

Preferences 9. Preferences

Review Questions. Unions and Collective Bargaining. Choose the letter that represents the BEST response.

ECON 200A: MICROECONOMICS ( DECISIONS )

Econ 201 Review Notes - Part 3

Final Exam - Solutions

Ecn Intermediate Microeconomic Theory University of California - Davis June 11, 2009 Instructor: John Parman. Final Exam

Managerial Economics, 01/12/2003. A Glossary of Terms

Many sellers: There are many firms competing for the same group of customers.

Textbook Media Press. CH 12 Taylor: Principles of Economics 3e 1

Static (or Simultaneous- Move) Games of Complete Information

Econ190 May 1, No baseball caps are allowed (turn it backwards if you have one on).

A new framework for digital publishing decisions 95. Alastair Dryburgh. Alastair Dryburgh 2003

Lecture 3 Allocation and Distribution

Capacity Dilemma: Economic Scale Size versus. Demand Fulfillment

LECTURE 1. MICROECONOMIC THEORY CONSUMER THEORY Preference and Choice. Lecturer: Andreas Papandreou

Final Exam - Solutions

Ph.D. MICROECONOMICS CORE EXAM January 2019

A Mixed-type Distribution for. Inventory Management

Demand Theory. Lecture VI and VII Utility Maximization, Choice, Demand (Varian Ch. 7, 8, 9, 10) Federico Trionfetti

Sponsored Search Markets

ECON 2100 (Fall 2018 Section 11) Exam #3B

ECON 2100 (Fall 2018 Section 11) Exam #3A

Economics 323 Microeconomic Theory Fall 2016

Economics 323 Microeconomic Theory Fall 2016

LECTURE NOTES ON MICROECONOMICS

Learning Objectives. Chapter 1. In this chapter you will

Modeling of competition in revenue management Petr Fiala 1

Chapter 14 TRADITIONAL MODELS OF IMPERFECT COMPETITION. Copyright 2005 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved.

****** 1. How is the demand for an input dependent upon the demand for an output? 2. Given a wage, how does a firm decide how many people to hire?

Prospect theory and investment decision behavior: A review

5/2/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 25: Recap 2. The Story So Far. Organization for the Week. Introduction

Final Exam - Solutions

Chapter 8: Exchange. 8.1: Introduction. 8.2: Exchange. 8.3: Individual A s Preferences and Endowments

CH short answer study questions Answer Section

Transcription:

Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only. Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use. This chapter was originally published in the book Handbook of Experimental Economics Results. The copy attached is provided by Elsevier for the author s benefit and for the benefit of the author s institution, for noncommercial research, and educational use. This includes without limitation use in instruction at your institution, distribution to specific colleagues, and providing a copy to your institution s administrator. All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including without limitation commercial reprints, selling or licensing copies or access, or posting on open internet sites, your personal or institution s website or repository, are prohibited. For exceptions, permission may be sought for such use through Elsevier s permissions site at: http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial James Andreoni and John H. Miller, Analyzing Choice with Revealed Preference: Is Altruism Rational?. In: C.R. Plott and V.L. Smitt, editors, Handbook of Experimental Economics Results, Volume 1. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 2008, p. 481. ISBN: 978-0-444-82642-8 Copyright 2008 Elsevier B.V.

Chapter 54 ANALYZING CHOICE WITH REVEALED PREFERENCE: IS ALTRUISM RATIONAL? JAMES ANDREONI Department of Economics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706, USA JOHN H. MILLER Department of Social and Decision Sciences, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA 1. Introduction In consumer theory, a binary preference ordering embodies three axioms of choice: it must be complete, reflexive and transitive. If preferences adhere to these axioms, then they can be characterized by a utility function. If preferences are well-behaved that is, they are convex and monotonic then the utility function will generate smooth downward sloping demand curves. How do we know if our fundamental assumptions are valid? Samuelson (1948) gave us an elegant answer to this question, the theory of revealed preference 1 : DEFINITION (Directly revealed preferred). An allocation X is directly revealed preferred to a different allocation Y if Y was in the budget set when X was chosen. Then if a well-behaved utility function could have generated the data, the data will satisfy WARP: WEAK AXIOM OF REVEALED PREFERENCE (WARP). If allocation X is directly revealed preferred to Y, then Y cannot be directly revealed preferred to X. WARP is a necessary condition on choices to be consistent with utility theory. However, it is not a sufficient condition. For this we need a stronger axiom. DEFINITION (Revealed preferred). If an allocation A is directly revealed preferred to B, B is directly revealed preferred to C, C is directly revealed preferred... to Z, and A and Z are not the same bundle, then A is revealed preferred to Z. That is, the revealed preferred relation is the transitive closure of the directly revealed preferred relation. 1 See Varian (1992) for a more detailed discussion of revealed preference. Handbook of Experimental Economics Results, Volume 1 Copyright 2008 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved DOI: 10.1016/S1574-0722(07)00054-6

482 J. Andreoni and J.H. Miller STRONG AXIOM OF REVEALED PREFERENCE (SARP). If allocation X is revealed preferred to Y, then Y will never be revealed preferred to X. If preferences are strictly convex, then choices will conform to SARP. Moreover, if choices conform to SARP then there exists a well-behaved preference ordering that could have generated the data. That is, utility theory is valid for the data observed. SARP is a strong tool for economists to use to verify that an individual s behavior is rational ; that is, it is consistent with neoclassical choice theory. However, SARP is still a bit restrictive in that it requires preferences to be strictly convex. Afriat (1967) and Varian (1982) showed that a fully general axiom that is both necessary and sufficient for the existence of a utility function even one that has flat spots on indifference curves is GARP: GENERALIZED AXIOM OF REVEALED PREFERENCE (GARP). If an allocation X is revealed preferred to Y, then Y is never strictly directly revealed preferred to X, that is, X is never strictly within the budget set when Y is chosen. In this chapter we discuss an application of revealed preference to a common occurrence in experiments kindness among subjects. In many experiments, including prisoner s dilemma, public goods, and bargaining experiments, subjects are often found to act benevolently toward each other. The immediate reaction when these findings began appearing was that subjects were irrational because they did not choose to maximize their own monetary payoffs. Some suggested that neoclassical theory had failed, and others suggested that economics needed to appeal to other behavioral sciences to understand this non-economic behavior. But the axioms of choice indicate that what is rational is what is consistent, that is, it can be characterized by convex preferences. Hence, whether this benevolent behavior is rational is an empirical question that the experimental economist is perfectly suited to answer. The hypothesis to explore here is that subjects have consistent preferences for altruism. To address this, we designed an experiment that would measure a subject s simple preferences over allocations between themselves and another subject. Most social dilemma experiments, like prisoner s dilemma, public goods, or alternating offer bargaining, can be decomposed into unilateral allocation problems. Since we see people allocating some of the payoff to themselves and some to the other subject, we pose this question: Can choices over this allocation process be rational? Let π s be the payoff a subject allocates to self and π o be the payoff the subject allocates to the other. Then the research question can be restated as, Can behavior in experiments be characterized by a quasi-concave utility function of the form U i = u i (π s,π o )?

Ch. 54: Analyzing Choice with Revealed Preference: Is Altruism Rational? 483 Table 1 This table lists the eight allocation decisions presented to the subjects. The decisions were presented in random order to each subject. Each decision can be thought of as choosing a payoff along a budget constraint. For each budget, a subject allocates the token endowment between himself and another subject. Tokens are redeemable for points at different rates for the two subjects. Hence, each allocation problem is a choice of final payoffs for the two subjects, where the price of the other s payoff in terms of self-payoff varies across budgets. We can then check to see that there are no violations of revealed preference, e.g., GARP, in which case the data on the subject is consistent with rational choice Budget Token endowment Points received for each token allocated Self Other 1 40 3 1 2 40 1 3 3 60 2 1 4 60 1 2 5 75 2 1 6 75 1 2 7 60 1 1 8 100 1 1 2. The Choice Task The data we describe here is a subset of that used our paper, Andreoni and Miller (2002). Subjects were presented eight different allocation tasks, in random order. Each choice endowed the subject with a budget of tokens which were worth different numbers of points to the two subjects. Points were all worth $0.10 to all subjects. The budget of tokens was 100, 75, 60 or 40 tokens, and tokens were worth 1, 2 or 3 points each. Hence, by varying the endowments and points, we were able to create various budgets of payoffs with different relative prices. The budgets were chosen to intersect often so as to give the strongest test of revealed preference. Table 1 presents the eight choices presented to subjects. After subjects made allocation decisions in all eight budgets, the experimenter randomly chose one to carry out with another subject chosen at random from the room. We ran four sessions of the experiment, each with 35 or 36 subjects, for a total of 142 subjects, and took great pains to protect the anonymity of all subjects. For details of the experiment and procedures, see Andreoni and Miller (2002). 3. Checking GARP Table 2 shows the violations of GARP. Over all 142 subjects, fewer than 10 percent had a single violation. For most of these subjects, however, the violations were minor. Altering a single choice by a single unit would eliminate all violations for all but 2 subjects, and

484 J. Andreoni and J.H. Miller Table 2 Here we list the subjects who showed at least one violation of the revealed preference axioms. Of the 142 subjects, fewer that 10% had any violations. Of those violations, most would disappear if one choice on one budget were moved by one token. Hence, only subject 40 showed serious violations of revealed preference. This implies that virtually all subjects display a rational demand for altruism Subject Number of violations WARP SARP GARP 3 1 3 3 38 2 4 4 40 3 10 10 41 1 1 1 47 1 1 3 61 1 4 4 72 1 1 1 87 1 1 1 90 1 1 1 104 1 2 2 126 1 3 1 137 1 1 1 139 1 1 1 moving two choices by 1 unit each would eliminate all but 1. 2 The only severe violation of revealed preference was subject 40. His choices are shown in Figure 1. For example, bundles A and B violate WARP, as do bundles A and C. However, bundles B and C also violate SARP and WARP. Given that virtually everyone s preferences can be rationalized, what do indifference curves look like? It turns out that 22 percent of subjects were perfectly selfish, keeping all of the endowment. Hence preferences of the form U = x s could characterize these people. Another 16 percent always split the payoffs exactly; hence Leontief utility, U = min{x s,x o }, could generate this data. Finally, 6 percent always allocated tokens to maximize the total payoff of subjects; that is, they were social maximizers. U = x s +x o could represent these people. This covers over a third of all subjects. The rest of the subjects were similar to these extreme cases but did not fit them exactly. Figure 2 illustrates an example of what we call a weakly selfish person someone with a bit more price sensitivity than a strong free rider. Figure 3 is a weakly Leontief person. She splits payoffs evenly or nearly evenly on all budgets. Finally, Figure 4 is a weak social maximizer. This person has very flat (but not perfectly flat) indifference curves. 2 We also conducted more sophisticated analysis of violations, including applying Afriat s Critical Cost Efficiency Index, which is a measure of how costly a violation of revealed preference is for the subject. This analysis, which can be found in Andreoni and Miller (2002) yielded a similar interpretation, that is, only subject 40 had severe violations.

Ch. 54: Analyzing Choice with Revealed Preference: Is Altruism Rational? 485 Figure 1. Of the subjects who had any violations of revealed preference axioms, only Subject 40, shown above, had severe violations that could not be eliminated with small adjustments to choices. For instance, A is directly revealed preferred to B, but B is directly revealed preferred to A. Likewise, A and C are directly revealed preferred to each other. Hence, A and B,andA and C violate WARP. Notice C is revealed preferred to B, but since B is directly revealed preferred to C,thenB and C violate GARP as well. For this subject, no quasiconcave utility function could rationalize the data. Figure 2. Over all 142 subjects, 22% were perfectly selfish, so U = x s could rationalize these choices. Another 22% were close to being perfectly selfish. Subject 45 shown here is typical of these. Most of the payoff is kept for himself, but there is still considerable price sensitivity. Overall we can characterize all individuals as one of these six types. 3 Table 3 shows the distribution of these preferences. 3 This characterization is based on minimizing the Euclidian distance between a subject s choices and those of one of the three exact utility functions, selfish, Leontief, and perfect substitutes. We also categorized people using a Bayesian criterion and by using an adaptive search algorithm. Each produced similar results.

486 J. Andreoni and J.H. Miller Figure 3. We found that 16% of subjects always divided the payoffs equally, hence U = min{x s,x o } could rationalize these choices. Another 18% had preferences that were very near to Leontief preferences but, like Subject 38 in this figure, deviated slightly from perfect Leontief preferences. Note that Subject 38 also violated WARP. However, the deviation (which appears likely to be an honest error) is not severe moving two of his choices by one token each would remove all violations. Figure 4. Six percent of subjects always gave all of the endowment to the subject with the highest redemption value, meaning the utility U = x s + x o would rationalize this data. Another 15% of subjects had preferences like Subject 1 above. They appear to have very flat indifference curves that generate choices near the socially maximal payoffs. 4. Conclusion This work illustrates that not all non-economic behavior is beyond economic analysis. Our maintained assumption as economists is that individual behavior is consistent with self-interest. At its weakest, self-interest only means that choices conform to some underlying preference ordering that is complete, reflexive and transitive, and, hence, some utility function can be used to describe behavior. However, the assumption of

Ch. 54: Analyzing Choice with Revealed Preference: Is Altruism Rational? 487 Table 3 Given that preferences are rational, what utility functions could have generated the observed behavior? By employing several different search algorithms, we found that six categories of utility functions could best characterize the data. There were three utility functions that fit a large fraction of the data precisely. The three other categories of preferences had preferences similar to the exact utility function, but differed some, as is illustrated in Figures 2, 3, and 4 Utility function Exact fit Weak fit Selfish: U i = π s 31 31 Leontief: U i = min{π s,π o } 23 26 Social maximizer: U i = π s + π o 8 22 self-interest does not tell us what variables are in that utility function. What does? Our methodology dictates that people themselves, through their actions, will do so. What we have shown here is that unselfish behavior in experiments can indeed be captured by a model of self-interested agents, but that self-interested agents are not always money-maximizing. When we define the choice set appropriately, unselfish acts can be described and predicted with the standard neoclassical model of choice. References Afriat, S. (1967). The construction of a utility function from expenditure data. Econometrica 6, 67 77. Andreoni, James, Miller, John H. (2002). Giving according to GARP: An experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica 70, 737 753. Samuelson, Paul A. (1948). Consumption theory in terms of revealed preference. Econometrica 15, 243 253. Varian, Hal R. (1982). The nonparametric approach to demand analysis. Econometrica 50, 945 972. Varian, Hal R. (1992). Microeconomic Analysis, third ed. Norton, New York.