The Mixed Strategy Equilibria and Adaptive Dynamics in the Bar Problem

Similar documents
CS 486/686 Lecture 17 2-Player Normal-Form Games 1. Determine dominant-strategy equilibria of a 2-player normal form game.

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Information Acquisition in Interdependent Value Auctions

Pricing in Dynamic Advance Reservation Games

Optimal Drafting in Professional Sports

Review from last. Econ 2230: Public Economics. Outline. 1. Dominant strategy implementation. Lecture 9: Mechanism Design lab evidence

Simple Market Equilibria with Rationally Inattentive Consumers

Uniform and Targeted Advertising with Shoppers and. Asymmetric Loyal Market Shares

University of Groningen. Investment evaluation with respect to commercial uncertainty Broens, Douwe Frits

GAME THEORY: Analysis of Strategic Thinking Exercises on Repeated and Bargaining Games

INDUSTRIAL ECONOMICS, WITH APPLICATIONS TO E-COMMERCE An Option for MSc Economics and MSc E-Commerce Autumn Term 2003

Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements. Online Appendix

Some Thoughts on the Traveler s Dilemma. 1 Introduction. 1.1 Statement of the problem. by Guillaume Alain

The Relevance of a Choice of Auction Format in a Competitive Environment

Existence of a Pareto optimal social interaction outcome with non-binary preferences

FIRST FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF WELFARE ECONOMICS

The Retailers Choices of Profit Strategies in a Cournot Duopoly: Relative Profit and Pure Profit

Strategic Alliances, Joint Investments, and Market Structure

Table A1.1: The Iteration Path Game

Learning by Observing

Notes on Intertemporal Consumption Choice

Harvard University Department of Economics

AN ASCENDING AUCTION FOR INTERDEPENDENT VALUES: UNIQUENESS AND ROBUSTNESS TO STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris

Introduction In recent research that explains the role of learning in labor market outcomes, authors typically assume uncertainty about a worker's abi

arxiv: v1 [econ.em] 12 Jul 2018

Competition: Boon or Bane for Reputation Building. Behavior. Somdutta Basu. October Abstract

Citation Journal of Integrated Creative Stud

University of Groningen. Effective monitoring and control with intelligent products Meyer, Gerben Gerald

Thinking About Chance & Probability Models

Citation for published version (APA): Kopányi, D. (2015). Bounded rationality and learning in market competition Amsterdam: Tinbergen Institute

Multiple Equilibria and Selection by Learning in an Applied Setting

underlying these concepts is more complex than the standard material taught in a principles class. The importance of network

The Oil Games OPEC Market Share Explained by Game Theory Episode 3 November 25, 2017

Agility in Repeated Games: An Example

> OPEC Market Share Explained by Game Theory

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Copyright (C) 2001 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the

Economics Letters 88 (2005) Efficient entry. Daniel Quint, Liran EinavT

The Price of Anarchy in an Exponential Multi-Server

arxiv: v2 [cs.gt] 5 May 2017

A Heuristic for Improved Genetic Bin Packing. Arthur L. CORCORAN and Roger L. WAINWRIGHT

Testing the Dinosaur Hypothesis under Empirical Datasets

An Approach to Predicting Passenger Operation Performance from Commuter System Performance

5 Market Games For Teaching Economics

Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona Department of Applied Economics

A TOPOLOGICAL CHARACTERIZATION OF THE KNOTTED AND LINKED PRODUCTS ARISING FROM SITE-SPECIFIC RECOMBINATION ON T (2, n)#c(2, r) DNA SUBSTRATES

Cooperation vs. Competition in R&D: the Role of Stability of Equilibrium

Supplimentary material for Research at the Auction Block: Problems for the Fair Benefits Approach to International Research

Test Codes: QEA and QEB (Both are of 'Descriptive' type) (Junior Research Fellowship in Quantitative Economics)

"Solutions" to Non-constant Sum Games

Market mechanisms and stochastic programming

Characterization of the Support of the Mixed. Strategy Price Equilibria in Oligopolies with. Heterogeneous Consumers

New Results for Lazy Bureaucrat Scheduling Problem. fa Sharif University of Technology. Oct. 10, 2001.

Symmetric Information Benchmark Begin by setting up a comparison situation, where there is no information asymmetry. Notation:

Game Theory DR. ÖZGÜR GÜRERK UNIVERSITY OF ERFURT WINTER TERM 2012/13. What can we model as a game?

WEAK AND STRICT DOMINANCE: A UNIFIED APPROACH

Two Lectures on Information Design

Existence of Nash equilibria in sporting contests with capacity constraints

CMSC 474, Introduction to Game Theory Analyzing Normal-Form Games

Notes on Introduction to Contract Theory

Utilizing Optimization Techniques to Enhance Cost and Schedule Risk Analysis

Unit3: Foundationsforinference. 1. Variability in estimates and CLT. Sta Fall Lab attendance & lateness Peer evaluations

Static (or Simultaneous- Move) Games of Complete Information

The social norm of leaving the toilet seat down: A game theoretic analysis

A Note on Costly Sequential Search and Oligopoly Pricing

Vying for Dominance: An Experiment in Dynamic Network Formation

CAF E: A Complex Adaptive Financial Environment. November 21, Abstract

Incentives in Crowdsourcing: A Game-theoretic Approach

Total /18 /18 /16 /15 /15 /18 /100. Economics 142 Final Exam NAME Vincent Crawford Winter 2008

Using Multi-chromosomes to Solve. Hans J. Pierrot and Robert Hinterding. Victoria University of Technology

Commitment and Con ict in Bilateral Bargaining

SI Game Theory, Fall 2008

Beliefs, Market Size and Consumer Search

Market Forces meet Behavioral Biases

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS AND STATISTICS Attempt all the questions. The allocation of marks is shown in brackets.

Methodology for the Design and Evaluation of Ontologies. Michael Gruninger and Mark S. Fox. University oftoronto. f gruninger, msf

A COMPARISON OF THE COURNOT AND STACKELBERG COMPETITION IN A MIXED DUOPOLY OF THE HIGHER EDUCATION MARKET. April 2012.

1. INTRODUCTION IS IT POSSIBLE TO MOVE THE COPPER MARKET? MATTI LISKI AND JUAN-PABLO MONTERO *

Equilibrium Selection and the Role of Information in Repeated. Matching Markets

Optimisation and Operations Research

Game Theory and Economics Prof. Dr. Debarshi Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

82 R. FISCHER AND L. MIRMAN sectors. It is then easy to make comparisons between the cooperative and the noncooperative solutions. This formulation al

Vertical Networks, Integration, and Connectivity

Strategic Analysis for Prediction Markets

Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with Contracts

Oligopoly Theory (11) Collusion

Adaptive Properties and Memory of a System of Interactive Agents: A Game Theoretic Approach

Equilibria in an infinite horizon game with an incumbent, entry and switching costs

Modeling of competition in revenue management Petr Fiala 1

HIERARCHICAL decision making problems arise naturally

Deliverable: D 4.1 Gap analysis against ISO 26262

Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements

Online Advertising, Retailer Platform Openness, and. Long Tail Sellers. 1 Introduction. Jianqing Chen. Zhiling Guo. The University of Texas at Dallas

A Simple Auction Mechanism for the Optimal Allocation of the Commons

Lecture 4: Will profits in reality be higher or lower than under Cournot? Tom Holden

Software Testing Education and Training in Hong Kong 1 2

Valuation Uncertainty and Imperfect Introspection in Second-Price Auctions

Oligopoly limit-pricing in the lab

Reaction Paper Influence Maximization in Social Networks: A Competitive Perspective

MERITOCRACY AS A MECHANISM IN THE CONTEXT OF VOLUNTARY CONTRIBUTION GAMES

TOPIC 4. ADVERSE SELECTION, SIGNALING, AND SCREENING

Transcription:

The Mixed Strategy Equilibria and Adaptive Dynamics in the Bar Problem John Q. Cheng SFI WORKING PAPER: 1996-08-063 SFI Working Papers contain accounts of scientific work of the author(s) and do not necessarily represent the views of the Santa Fe Institute. We accept papers intended for publication in peer-reviewed journals or proceedings volumes, but not papers that have already appeared in print. Except for papers by our external faculty, papers must be based on work done at SFI, inspired by an invited visit to or collaboration at SFI, or funded by an SFI grant. NOTICE: This working paper is included by permission of the contributing author(s) as a means to ensure timely distribution of the scholarly and technical work on a non-commercial basis. Copyright and all rights therein are maintained by the author(s). It is understood that all persons copying this information will adhere to the terms and constraints invoked by each author's copyright. These works may be reposted only with the explicit permission of the copyright holder. www.santafe.edu SANTA FE INSTITUTE

The mixed strategy equilibria and adaptive dynamics in the Bar Problem (extended draft) John Cheng Department ofeconomics University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI 48109 jcheng@econ.lsa.umich.edu January 4, 1997 Abstract This paper looks at an N-person coordination game which is called by Brian Arthur as the bar problem. We look at the mixed strategy equilibria and show that there is a unique purely mixed strategy equilibrium in which all players play non-degenerated mixed strategies. We also examine some simple dynamics that might evolve the system to that equilibrium by conducting some preliminary numerical experiments. The results show that under usual initial conditions the system will converge to the unique mixed strategy equilibrium. This paper summarizes the project I did during the 1995 Santa Fe Institute Computational Economics Workshop. Special thanks to the organizers of the Workshop, John Miller and Scott Page. I also wish to thank fellow workshop participants, especially Nick Feltovich and Jordan Rapporport, for their very helpful comments and suggestions.

1 Introduction Brian Arthur[?] used a very simple yet interesting problem to illustrate eective uses of inductive reasoning as well as computational methods in economics research. Our interest here is to examine Arthur's example (called by Arthur as the Bar Problem) from a dierent angle. There is a bar called El Farol in downtown Santa Fe. There are n agents interested in going to the bar each night. All agents have identical preferences. Each ofthem will enjoy the night atel Farol very much if there are no more than m agents in the bar however, each of them will suer miserably if there are more than m agents. In Arthur's example, the total number of agents is 100, and the threshold number m = 60. The only information available to agents is the number of visitors to the bar in previous nights. The payos would be 1 for each agent who made the right choice at any particular night (i.e., go to the bar when the total number of agents going is less than or equal to m, orstaying at home if the total attendance turns out to be more than m) for those made the wrong choice, the payo would be 0. We call this the BP game. Arthur investigated the number of agents attending the bar over time by using a diverse population of simple rule based agents. One interesting result he obtained is that over time, the average attendance of the bar is about 60. 1 Arthur examined the dynamic driving force behind this \equilibrium", but he did not give a precise mathematical explanation in his paper. Our interest here is the mixed-strategy equilibria in this coordination game, and the possible dynamic processes that could lead to such equilibria. I will characterize some preliminary results in the following sections. I shall start with some theoretical analysis and discuss some computer experiments we have conducted. The BP game and its equilibria The bar problem is in the essence a N-agent coordination game in which eachagenthastwo possible pure strategies. We are all familiar with the coordination game with symmetric payos. 3 There are two pure strategy Nash equilibria and one mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. As the number of players go up in this symmetric pure coordination game, the number of pure strategy equilibria goes up quickly. In the Bar Problem, the number of pure strategy Nash equilibria is Cn m,which is the possible number of ways to pick m out of n agents..1 Strategic complementarity The BP game is in fact a game with strategic complementarity, using the denition in Milgrom and Shannon[?]. It is straightforward to check that this game with its payo structure satised the so called \single crossing property" and some other related conditions, and therefore has the desired strategic complementarity. (For the denition of \single crossing property", see [?].) In Milgrom and Roberts[?], it is shown as a theorem that in any adaptive and sophisticated learning process (as dened in their paper) associated with a normal form game, the strategies of players will eventually stay in a region 4 dened by the set of pure strategy Nash equilibria of that underlying normal form game, provided that the game is one with strategic complementarity. 1 Arthur did point out in his paper that this could be explained as each agents playing a mixed strategy. All results presented in this paper were obtained while attending the Santa Fe workshop. 3 We restrict attention to games with symmetric payos in this paper. 4 The size of the region is the key. 1

While this provides powerful insights and results for learning and dynamic processes in some games, it doesn't tell us much about the BP game. Because there are so many pure strategy Nash equilibria in the BP game, the target region (see Milgrom and Roberts[?] for the precise denition) dened by the pure strategy Nash equilibria is in fact the whole strategy space. Hence the theorem mentioned above by Milgrom and Roberts wouldn't help too much in the BP game.. Mixed strategy equilibria We discuss the number of mixed strategy Nash equilibria in the BP game. Dene It is easy to verify that 5 F (m n ) 0 C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;1;i F (m n 0) = 1 F (m n 1) = 0 Proposition 1 Proof. 1 F = @ @ ( C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;1;i ) = = i=1 i=1 i C i n;1 i;1 (1 ; ) n;1;i ; @F @ < 0 (n ; 1) C i;1 n; i;1 (1 ; ) n;1;i ; m; = (n ; 1)[ j=0 C j n; j (1 ; ) n;;j ; (n ; 1 ; i) C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;;i = (n ; 1) (;1)C n; (1 ; ) n; < 0 (n ; 1) C i n; i (1 ; ) n;;i C i n; i (1 ; ) n;;i ] here j = i ; 1: If in a mixed strategy equilibrium, all players are choosing the same \mixing", then we call it a symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium. As to the number of mixed strategy equilibria in the BP game, we have the following result. Proposition The number of symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium in the bar problem is one. 5 strictly speaking, this should be lim!0 F (m n ) =1.

Proof. Let us consider the situation with a total number of agents being n and the threshold number being m, assuming n>m. In a symmetric equilibrium, all agents choose the same probability of going to the bar, which we denote as. In such a situation, we must have the following condition which says that each agent is indierent between going and staying. 1 C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;1;i =1 n;1 i=m C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;1;i The left hand side is the payo of an agent if it chooses to go, the right hand side is its payo if it chooses to stay. Notice that the sum of both sides is exactly one. Therefore we know, or C i n;1 i (1 ; ) n;1;i = 1 F (m n ) = 1 Since F (m n ) is a continuous function in, and F < 0, F (m n ) = 1 has a unique solution. Hence the number of symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium is one. The next result goes a little further. Proposition 3 In a mixed strategy equilibrium of the BP game, if no agent plays pure strategy, then all agents must play the same mixed strategy. Proof. 3 We take advantage of the fact that there are only two pure strategies available to each agent. If there are two agents using dierent strategies in amixed strategy equilibrium, we can denote them as agent 1 and, and their probability of going to the bar as 1 and. It must be that 1 6=. Let us use T to denote the group of all players other than players 1 and. Since player 1 is using a mixed strategy, it must be that the probability of more than m-1 players show up, given T and, equals 1. Since it has to be true that both events of more than m ; 1 agents show up and no more thanm ; 1 agents show up are equally likely, given the strategies of T and player. Likewise, player is also using a mixed strategy. It follows that the probability of more than m-1 players show up, given T and 1, equals 1. Since it has to be true that both events of more than m ; 1 agents show up and no more than m ; 1 agents show up are equally likely, given the strategies of T and player 1. Since all agents decide independently in a mixed strategy equilibrium, and 1 6=, the conclusion of the above two paragraphs cannot both be true.for example, if 1 >, and the probability of more than m-1 players show up equals 1 ( given T and ), then it is impossible to have the probability of more than m-1 players show up, given T and 1, also equals 1. Notice that agents only have two available pure strategies. This contradiction tells us that in an equilibrium where all agents play mixed strategies, they must be playing the same mixed strategy. Combining the previous two propositions, we know that there is a unique equilibrium in the BP game in which all players play (the same) non-degenerated mixed strategy. 3

3 Agents with mixed strategy Since we know that the BP game has only one mixed strategy equilibrium (MNE) and many pure strategy equilibria (PNE), it is natural to conjecture that the unique MNE is a focal point of the game. In particular, we are interested to see if any population of agents playing mixed strategies facing selection pressure will evolve to the state in which all agents play the MNE strategy. The reasons that we are interested in agents using mixed strategy are summarized as the following: 1. No agent can commit to any single pure strategy, especially when dealing with a large population. (More dicult to achieve coordination as the number of agents increase.). Agents could appear to be using mixed strategies. 3. Reasonable agents might believe their own analysis only to some degree, thus might some doubts about their own prediction. Mixed strategy captures this degree of doubt, with pure strategies as the limiting beliefs. 4. The use of behavioral mixed strategy, at least to some people, seems reasonable when agents have to make decisions under uncertainty. 5. The use of mixed strategy in the BP game seems no more unreasonable than the use of, say, the use of myopic optimization in evolutionary games. We used some computational experiments to investigate whether agents playing mixed strategies will end up in the MNE. 4 Computational experiments 4.1 The set up We 6 conducted some numerical experiments with 100 agents, each of them are restrict to select a mixed strategy from the interval of [0 1]. The threshold number is set to be 60. Agents are randomly assigned a number from [0 1] as their initial strategy, which is just the probability of going to the bar. Let's denote this number as i for agent i. These are the initial conditions of our experiments. Then, in each round, agents decide whether they want to go to the bar by drawing a number randomly from [0 1], and compare this number with their 's. If i is larger than the number agent i drew, it would decide to go to the bar if not, it would choose to stay. In each round, each agent would receive a score of 1 if it made the right choice and 0 if it made the wrong choice. Whether their choices are right or wrong depends on the threshold value, other agents' choices, and their own choices. Each generation of agents can live for 10 periods. 7 At the end of each generation, all agents are ranked by their accumulative score. 6 I am grateful to David Kane, Micheal Herron, and other fellow participants in the Santa Fe workshop for helping me with important computational issues. 7 10 is an arbitrary choice and can be changed to other numbers. 4

The selection procedure we used in our experiments is very simple: take the top 50 percent 8 of agents and eliminate the rest. We duplicate each of the surviving agent to get anewgroup of 100 agents. The next step is to allow mutation in agent's strategy. It is done by rst choosing a random number from the interval [;b +b], where b is randomly chosen from 0 to 0:01. Then add this number to the number that representing the current strategy of an agent, with the restriction that all strategies have to remain in the interval [0 1]. Now wehave anewgeneration of 100 agents. 9 In each of our experiment, we ran this set up for a large number of generations to obtain the nal outcome. 4. The results The preliminary experiments we ran involved either 1000 or 100 000 generations. The outcomes for the experiments with 100 000 generations indicate that the nal strategies of agents are within some tolerance of the MNE strategy, regardless of the initial condition of the experiments (i.e., the distribution of the initial strategies of the agents). The outcomes for the experiments with 1000 generations indicate some sign of convergence. Instead of collapsing into a region around the MNE strategy, the nal strategies of agents often (in most cases) have two \accumulation" points. 5 Conclusion and further research directions Systematic experiments are yet to be conducted to gain more insights and results about the transition to the mixed strategy equilibrium. The results of the preliminary experiments indicates that the unique mixed strategy Nash equilibrium is an attraction point for agents playing the BP game. The uniqueness plays an important role here. Some of the experimental set-up could be modied, and suggestions have been made to incorporate random mutation steps and more variations of the initial conditions. There are many important issues this paper chose not to explore, some of them could generate further interesting results. These issues include: Incorporate the possibility that agents' actions are correlated by some public signal. Incorporate more systematic learning into agents' strategy. Have a population of heterogeneous agents. Consider more complex stage games. In particular, consider games where agents have more than possible pure strategies and/or games with asymmetric payos. 8 we also experimented with other non-trivial (neither 0 nor 1) percentages, and the result are qualitatively the same. 9 There could be many otherways to apply a selection pressure on the agent population, but our experiments conducted were restricted in using only the method mentioned above. 5