The Core Pareto Optimality and Social Welfare Maximizationty

Similar documents
General Equilibrium for the Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/9 (Lecture 9, Micro Theory I)

The 2x2 Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/10/2 (Lecture 8, Micro Theory I)

The 2x2 Exchange Economy. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2012/11/21 (Lecture 2, Micro Theory I)

Lecture Notes, Econ G30D: General Equilibrium and the Welfare Theorems

Lecture Notes, Econ 320B. Set # 5.

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 7

Advanced Microeconomics

FIRST FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF WELFARE ECONOMICS

Luca Spataro Lectures 2. Public Economics. Efficiency (Ref. Myles 1995, ch. 2) March 2015, University of Pisa

5/2/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 25: Recap 2. The Story So Far. Organization for the Week. Introduction

Equilibrium and E ciency

Shadow Prices. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2013/9/13. (Lecture 2, Micro Theory I)

WELFARE PROPERTIES OF JUNGLE EXCHANGE

1 Mechanism Design (incentive-aware algorithms, inverse game theory)

Supporting Prices and Convexity. Joseph Tao-yi Wang 2012/9/12 (Lecture 1, Micro Theory I)

Welfare Economics. Philip A. Viton. May 17, Philip A. Viton CRP 781 () Welfare May 17, / 1

1 Mechanism Design (incentive-aware algorithms, inverse game theory)

A Consistent Firm Objective When Markets are Incomplete: Profit Maximization

1 Mechanism Design (incentive-aware algorithms, inverse game theory)

Adam Smith Theorem. Lecture 9 Monday, Sept 28. Lecture. 1. More about Pareto Efficiency. 1. Midterm two weeks from today. In class, Monday, Oct 12.

Attribute Theory of Consumer Behavior

1 Competitive Equilibrium

Economics 384 A1. Intermediate Microeconomics II. Review Questions 1. S Landon Fall 2007

A SIMPLE ECONOMY. MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell. Note: the detail in slides marked * can only be seen if you run the slideshow

Introduction to Microeconomic Theory

Activity Rules and Equilibria in the Combinatorial Clock Auction

Tools of Normative Analysis

Chapter 8: Exchange. 8.1: Introduction. 8.2: Exchange. 8.3: Individual A s Preferences and Endowments

Public Economics by Luca Spataro. Market failures: Externalities (Myles ch. 10. sections 4.4, 5, 7.2 & 7.3 excluded)

Externalities in the Koopmans Diagram

Rationing Poor Consumers to Reduce Prices

Section 1: Introduction

Perfect Competition Definition

Lecture 3 Allocation and Distribution

Existence of a Pareto optimal social interaction outcome with non-binary preferences

Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with Contracts

Exercise 2. Jan Abrell Centre for Energy Policy and Economics (CEPE) D-MTEC, ETH Zurich. Exercise

Chapters 1 and 2 Trade Without Money and A Model of Money

EconS Second-Degree Price Discrimination

The Efficient Allocation of Individuals to Positions

Third Degree. Distinguish from First-Degree or Perfect Price Discrimation

Modeling of competition in revenue management Petr Fiala 1

Welfare economics. Lecture note 5

Lecture 14. A Closed-Economy One-Period Macroeconomic Model. Randall Romero Aguilar, PhD I Semestre 2017 Last updated: June 27, 2017

Managing Decentralized Inventory and Transhipment

Robust Supply Function Bidding in Electricity Markets With Renewables

Overcoming the Limitations of Utility Design for Multiagent Systems

Powered by TCPDF (

The Need for Information

Friedrich von Hayek and mechanism design

The Efficiency of Voluntary Pollution Abatement when Countries can Commit

The Need for Information

Economics 361 Assessment

Outline. Introduction. ciency. Excise Tax. Subsidy 2/29

ECON Chapter 5: A Closed-Economy One-Period Macroeconomic Model (Part 1)

Satisficing. Search and Satisficing. Satisficing as Optimal Stopping. Can also be derived as optimal behavior as a simple sequential

Network Flows. 7. Multicommodity Flows Problems. Fall 2010 Instructor: Dr. Masoud Yaghini

International Negotiations for Reducing Greenhouse Gases with Emission Permits Trading

Equilibrium and Efficiency

Industrial Organization Entry Costs, Market Structure and Welfare

PARETO-IMPROVING CONGESTION PRICING AND REVENUE REFUNDING WITH ELASTIC DEMAND

General Examination in Microeconomic Theory

Ph.D. MICROECONOMICS CORE EXAM August IMPORTANT. You are expected to adhere to the following guidelines in completing the exam:

Learning Outcomes Assessment. Instructor: Timothy Dang Academic year Economics 361

LECTURE 13 THE NEOCLASSICAL OR WALRASIAN EQUILIBRIUM INTRODUCTION

Water Resource Economics C H A P T E R A W A T E R D E M A N D, S U P P L Y, A N D A L L O C A T I O N

Welfare properties of argumentation-based semantics 1

Computationally Feasible VCG Mechanisms. by Alpha Chau (feat. MC Bryce Wiedenbeck)

Intro to Algorithmic Economics, Fall 2013 Lecture 1

The Retail Space-Exchange Problem with. Pricing and Space Allocation Decisions 1

1.. There are two firms that produce a homogeneous product. Let p i

Learning by Observing

Non-decreasing Payment Rules in Combinatorial Auctions

TUTORIAL 10 Welfare. Intermediate Microeconomics, Spring Massimo Scotti

Lectures Notes on General Equilibrium

Adam Smith Theorem. Lecture 4(ii) Announcements. Lecture. 0. Link between efficiency and the market allocation.

Taste-homogeneity of Optimal Jurisdictions in a Tiebout Economy with Crowding Types and Endogenous Educational Investment Choices

6) Consumer surplus is the red area in the following graph. It is 0.5*5*5=12.5. The answer is C.

INTRODUCTION TO WALRASIAN GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM MODELING. Structural and Behavioral Underpinnings of the Walrasian General Equilibrium Model

Using this information, we then write the output of a firm as

Powered by TCPDF (

Spatial Price Integration in Competitive Markets with Capacitated Transportation Networks. (Ian) Yihang Zhu

1 Applying the Competitive Model. 2 Consumer welfare. These notes essentially correspond to chapter 9 of the text.

Coase Revisited: Economic Efficiency under Externalities, Transaction Costs and Non-Convexity

Econ Microeconomics Notes

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction and maximization

Competition between wireless service providers sharing a radio resource

Domestic and International Strategic Interactions in Environment Policy Formation

Demand Theory. Lecture VI and VII Utility Maximization, Choice, Demand (Varian Ch. 7, 8, 9, 10) Federico Trionfetti

MARKETS AND MARKET FAILURES

Money and Credit with Limited Commitment and Theft

Robust Multi-unit Auction Protocol against False-name Bids

The Price of Anarchy in an Exponential Multi-Server

Econ 101, ch 31, Exchange

Brown University ECON 1130, Intermediate Microeconomics (Mathematical) Spring 2017 Class meets Tuesdays and Thursdays, 1:00-2:30 p.m.

Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems* 2015/2016. Lecture Reaching Agreements

Counterfeiting as Private Money in Mechanism Design

14.03 Fall 2004 Problem Set 3

How does state ownership affect optimal export taxes? Abstract

Transcription:

The Core Pareto Optimality and Social Welfare Maximizationty Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 14, October 19 Outline 1 The Core 2 Core, indiviual rationality, and Pareto effi ciency 3 Social welfare function 4 Pareto optimality and social welfare maximization

From Last Class Firm j = 1,..., J are described by a production set, Y j R L. Consumers i = 1,..., I are described by a consumption set X i R L +, preferences i, endowments ω i X i, and shares θ i [0, 1] J of the profits of each firm (with 1 = i θ ij). For a while we will not care about firm ownership. An allocation: (x, y) R L(I +J) where x i X i for each i = 1,..., I, and y j Y j for each j = 1,..., J. An allocation (x, y) is feasible if I x i I ω i + J j=1 y j An allocation (x, y) is individually rational if x i i ω i for all i. Definition A feasible allocation (x, y) is Pareto optimal (effi cient) if there is no other feasible allocation (x, y ) such that x i i x i for all i = 1,..., I and x i i x i for some i

Coalitions and Blocking We can think of a different notion of making everyone happy which takes into account individual rationality as well as some notion of individuals making their own choices. This is easier to define for an exchange economy: let J = 1, and Y J = R L +. Definition A coalition is a subset of {1,..., I }. Definition A coalition S {1,..., I } blocks the allocation x if for each i S there exist x i X i such that x i i x i for all i S and x i ω i i S i S A blocking coalition can make all its members better off. One can think of a weaker definition where a coalition benefits at least one of its members strictly without hurting the others.

The Core Next, we define the idea that no group of consumers can gain by seceding from the economy. Definition A feasible allocation x is in the core of an economy if there is no coalition that blocks it. The idea is that no sub-group of consumers can improve their situation by separating from the economy. One could define these concepts with firms, but things get complicated in defining what is feasible for a particular coalition as one needs to allocate production.

Pareto Optimality, Individual Rationality, and the Core Easy to Prove Results Any allocation in the core of an economy is also Pareto optimal. Obvious since the whole (sometimes called grand coalition S = {1,..., I }) is not a blocking coalition. Not all Pareto optimal allocations are in the core. Slightly less obvious: x i = ω (consumer i gets everything) is Pareto optimal but not in the core. Any assumptions requred here? In an Edgeworth box, the core is the set of all individually rational Pareto optimal allocations. This is an (easy) homework problem. With more consumers this result does not hold. As the number of consumers grows, there are more possible coalitions, and more allocations will be blocked. So the core is typically much smaller than the set of Pareto optimal allocations that are individually rational.

Characterization of Pareto Optimal Allocations Definitions are well and good, but how do we know Pareto optimal allocations exist? Furthermore, how do we find Pareto optimal allocations? To answer these questions, we restrict attention to the case of continuous, complete, and transitive preference relations, so that one can work with individuals utility functions. Existence turns out to be an easy problem. Characterization goes through a particular maximization problem: an allocation is Pareto optimal if and only if it maximizes a particular welfare function that econmpasses everyone s utility.

Definitions With Utility Functions Suppose individuals preferences are represented by a utility function. Consumer i s utility function is denoted u i (x i ). We can rewrite Pareto effi ciency and individual rationality as follows. Definitions with utility functions A feasible allocation (x, y) is Pareto optimal if there is no other feasible allocation (x, y ) such that u i (x i ) u i (x i ) for all i and u i (x i ) > u i (x i ) for some i. A feasible allocation (x, y) is individually rational if u i (x i ) u i (ω i ) for all i.

Do Pareto Optimal Allocations Exist? Pareto optimal allocations exist if the set of feasible allocations is well behaved. Theorem Any economy such that the set of feasible allocations is non-empty, closed, and compact, and each i is complete, transitive, and continuous, has a Pareto effi cient allocation. Proof. Let A be the set of feasible allocations; let U : A R be defined by U(x, y) = u i (x i ) This is well defined because, by Debreu s theorem, each i can be represented by a continuous function u i. U is the sum of continuous functions, thus it is also continuous. Since A is compact and nonempty, the Extreme Value Theorem implies that there is a feasible allocation that maximizes U. This allocation must be Pareto optimal because if another feasible allocation Pareto dominates it, that allocation must give a larger value of U, implying that someone reaches a higher utility value for that allocation.

Pareto Effi ciency and Utility Possibility Set Definitions The utility possibility set is { U = (v 1,..., v I ) R I : The utility possibility frontier is there exists a feasible (x, y) such that v i u(x i ) for i = 1,..., I UF = {( v 1,..., v I ) U : there is no v U such that v > v} } Draw a picture for an Edgeworth box economy. The utility possibility frontier is the boundary of U, and a Pareto optimal allocation must belong to the frontier. In the picture, a point on the frontier can be characterized as the solution to the following optimization problem max (x,y ) is a feasible allocation u i (x i ) such that u j (x j ) v j for j i If an allocation is Pareto effi cient then it maximizes the utility of one consumer subject to the constraint that all others get some fixed (feasible) amount.

Social Welfare and Planner s Problem Definitions A (linear) social welfare function is a weighted sum of the individuals utilities: W = λ i u i = λ v with λ i 0 The social welfare maximization problem is max v U i λ i v i This maximization problem is sometimes called the planner s problem. There is another planner s problem, that correspond to maximizing the utility of one consumer, subject to all other consumers getting a predifined utility value.

Pareto Effi ciency and Social Welfare One can use the planner s problem to find Pareto optimal allocations. Theorem { } {u i, ω i } I, {Y j } J j=1 and If the allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is feasible for the economy E = solves the problem λ i u i (x i ) where λ i > 0 for all i max (x,y ) is a feasible allocation then (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal. Proof. By contradiction. Suppose (ˆx, ŷ) is not Pareto optimal. Then, it is Pareto dominated by some feasible allocation (x, y). Since the λ i are all strictly positive, we must have λ i u i (x i ) > λ i u i (ˆx i ) But this means (ˆx, ŷ) does not maximize I λ i u i (x i ) which is a contradiction.

Pareto Effi ciency and Social Welfare Theorem { } {u i, ω i } I, {Y j } J j=1 and If the allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is feasible for the economy E = solves the problem λ i u i (x i ) where λ i > 0 for all i max (x,y ) is a feasible allocation then (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal. Notice that if a feasible allocation maximizes I λ i u i (x i ) it also maximizes K I λ i u i (x i ) where K is a strictly positive number. So, without loss of generality we can consider the social welfare function λ i I λ u i (x i ) = ˆλ i u i (x i ) where ˆλ i 0 for all i and ˆλ i = 1 i In other words, a Pareto optimal allocation maximizes a weighted sum of individual utilities.

Planner s Problem: Examples Draw the utility possibility set and solve the planner s problem in an Edgeworth box economy. Note that the objective function is linear. Draw the utility possibility set and solve the planner s problem in a Robinson Crusoe economy. The objective function is not linear here... why the difference?

Pareto Effi ciency and Constrained Planner Problem Theorem { } {u i, ω i } I, {Y j } J j=1 and If the allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is feasible for the economy E = solves the problem λ i u i (x i ) where λ i > 0 for all i max (x,y ) is a feasible allocation then (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal. In order for the this to be a full characterization result, one would like to prove a converse: if an allocation is Pareto optimal, then it must solve the planner s problem. This works if given a Pareto optimal allocation one can always find some weights that make it a solution to the planner s problem. That kind of result needs more assumptions, and even with those, it cannot guarantee that everyone gets a non-zero weight in the social welfare function.

Social Welfare Maximization and Pareto Effi ciency Consider the linear social welfare function W (x, y) = I λ i u i (x i ) where λ i 0 for all i and (x, y) is an allocation. One can think of W (x, y) as the composition of two functions: U : A R I, defined as U(x, y) = (u 1(x 1),..., u I (x I )), and f : R I R, defined as f (v) = I λi vi, where A is the set of allocations. Using the dot product notation, f (v ) = λ v. Then, W (x, y) = f (U(x, y)). The image of the set of feasible allocations under the mapping U is given by: V = { U(x, y) R I : (x, y) is a feasible allocation } Remark U and V are not the same set: The utility possibility set U is equal to V plus all the points dominated by points in V U is a larger set.

Social Welfare Maximization and Pareto Effi ciency Proposition The allocation (ˆx, ŷ) solves the problem max W (x, y) (x,y ) is a feasible allocation if and only if the vector ˆv = U (ˆx, ŷ) solves the problem max v V λ v. Proof. Question 4, Problem set 7. Given this poposition, any Pareto optimal allocation maximizes λ v over the set V. Under what conditions can we say that for any Pareto optimal allocation there exists a vector λ such that ˆv maximizes the desired dot product in that set. The tool that yields this result is (a version of) the separating hyperplane theorem. But to get there we need a math refresher.

Next Week Separating Hyperplane Theorem. Any Pareto optimal allocation maximizes the social welfare function. Markets and Competitive Equilibrium.